Business Ethics: A European Review Volume 16 Number 3 July 2007

Singular justice and software piracy Lucas D.Intronan Introduction To act with moral courage is very difficult, almost impossible. To know the right thing to do is not the same as doing the right thing – as is evident from the many corporate scandals that have occurred in recent years. When we encourage ethical conduct, we want individuals to act morally rather than to know morality (Jones et al. 2005). It is with this supposition that this paper will proceed. It seems rather evident that proposing (even preaching) ethical codes, principles, categorical imperatives and the like does very little to extend the sphere of moral action – as Enron1 reminded us. We can sharpen moral reasoning by reasoning about cases, and this may or may not be beneficial. However, ethics for the ordinary ‘getting through everyday life’ person does not come before her as cases to be solved. Rather ethical claims jump at her ‘as from nowhere’ (Caputo 1993). They leap at her in the most unexpected places and times. When she is rushing for the train, or pressing against some impossible deadline, they appear not as cases to be reasoned but as claims to be responded to, or not. Ethics as moral reasoning seems always to arrive too late, like the onlookers after an accident. Nonetheless, it is in accidents rather than after or before accidents that ethics really matters. It is for this reason that I will argue in the first section of this paper, using the work of Levinas, that ethics is not a branch of philosophy in the Professor of Organization, Technology and Ethics, Department of Organization, Work and Technology, Lancaster University Management School, UK.

n

264

way that epistemology or aesthetics is a branch of philosophy. I will argue that ethics is rather the very source of our sociality. The question ‘what ought I do?’ comes up, first and foremost, as a desperate plea, by the self-certain ego, shaken, immediately and absolutely, by the naked face of the Other before her, ‘here and now’. Responding to the Other is not a choice borne out by reason, but the ongoing releasing of my rights, to accept my guilt, to be ‘for the Other’, her hostage. Ethical responsibility, the claim of the Other, cannot be enforced, it can only be accepted, in absolute passivity. Yes, but what about justice, one could hear the other Others ask, even plea? What about those who do not face me ‘here and now’ but who could all equally face me; surely, they have an equal claim to my responsibility? Surely, I am ‘for them’ as well. In the second section of the paper, I will argue with Levinas and Derrida that the face of the Other does not only signify its own Otherness but it also immediately and simultaneously reminds me of every other Other. As such, the radical asymmetry of the ethical claim immediately and simultaneously recalls the symmetrical claim for justice – even I am Other for others. The community of Others require justice – justification through calculation, principles and laws – to ensure equality in distribution and utilization of resources. However, the strength of such a justice is not in its disregard for the idiosyncratic in its search for the universal categories and principles of equality, fairness and the like. Rather, its strength is in its steadfast willingness to be disrupted by the proximity of the Other. Ethics is what makes justice a serious question rather than a mere r 2007 The Author Journal compilation r 2007 Blackwell Publishing Ltd, 9600 Garsington Road, Oxford, OX4 2DQ, UK and 350 Main St, Malden, MA 02148, USA

Business Ethics: A European Review Volume 16 Number 3 July 2007

calculation. As Levinas (1991/1974: 159) expresses so eloquently: ‘Justice remains justice only, in a society where there is no distinction between those close and those far off, but in which there also remains the impossibility of passing by the closest’. I will use the work of Derrida to articulate a notion of singular justice as exactly that justice ‘where there is no distinction between those close and those far off, but in which there also remains the impossibility of passing by the closest’. In the final section of the paper, I will attempt to make sense of this double claim, this impossible possibility of singular justice, by dealing with a singular case of intellectual property rights and software piracy. I hope to demonstrate that Levinasian ethics presents us with some fundamental and radical way to (almost) do ethics rather than merely knowing ethics.

Asymmetry and infinite responsibility For Levinas (1989, 1991/1974, 1996c) and Caputo (1993), ethics is not a cognitive content, the outcome of some practical or moral reasoning process as proposed, for example, by Kant (1785). Caputo (1993, 2000) argues that moral reasoning comes too late – like a crowd after an accident that now argues about what went wrong, who is to blame, what we ought to have done – so too with ethical theorists/theory. Rather, in the facticity of everyday life, moral claims jump at us from nowhere. They make claims on our resources without leaving us time and space to reason and discover what we ought to do. The temporality and location of the ethical claim is of a different kind from the temporality and location of moral reasoning – it has an urgency that closes down all room for manoeuvre (Introna 2002). The temporality and location of the ethical claim is in my ‘finding myself already busy in the world of everyday going about’. Ethics happens, and when I look up, take notice, I am already ‘in’ it – its captive, its hostage. How will I respond, now here, to the face before me? For Levinas, ethics first and foremost implicates me – it is a burden I cannot defer. Ethics is not r 2007 The Author Journal compilation r 2007 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

guidelines for ‘them’ or even for ‘us’. Its addressee is none other than this singular me – I am the responsible one. The almost intolerable burden of the Other is always already mine. But what is this burden? Where does it emanate from? Levinas (1989: 82) argues that it is tied to the very constitution of the I: ‘one has to speak, to say I, to be in the first person, precisely to be me (moi). But, from that point, in affirming this me being, one has to respond to one’s right to be’. In other words, when saying ‘I’ there is an implicit claim of the right to be that always already refers to the claim of the other that demands responding to – my responsibility. Thus, before saying ‘I’, before being, the ‘I’ is already tied to the claim of the other. This is why Levinas argues that the word ‘I’ does not first and foremost stand for a sovereign I, but rather for a ‘here I am’ that is the response to the other – a ‘here I am’ that makes me more responsible than any other. As such, responsibility for the other is ‘the essential, primary and fundamental structure of subjectivity . . . the very node of subjectivity is knotted in ethics understood as responsibility’ (Levinas 1985: 95). How does the Other entangled in the subject, at its origin, appeal to me, disturb me? For Levinas, ethics happens – or not – when the self-certain ego becomes disturbed – shaken and fundamentally questioned – by the proximity, before me, of the absolute Other, the absolute singular (the Infinite); ‘[w]e name this calling into question of my spontaneity by the presence of the Other, ethics’ (1967: 43). The wholly Other that takes me by surprise, overturns and overflows my categories, themes and concepts; it shatters their walls, makes their evident sense explode into nonsense. For Levinas, the claim of conventional ethics (Ethics with a big ‘E’ as Caputo calls it) that we can know the right thing to do is to claim that the absolute singular can become absorbed into, domesticated by, the categories of my consciousness. Once the Other, this singular face before me, has become an instance in my categories or themes, it (the face) can no longer disturb the self-evidentness of those categories. Nothing is more self-evident than my categories and likewise with the singular now absorbed as an instance of them (Introna 2001, 2003). As a male, female,

265

Business Ethics: A European Review Volume 16 Number 3 July 2007

Jew, black, white, rich, poor, homeless, rapist, criminal, capitalist, idealist, realist (and every other category we care to name), the singular disturbing face disappears in the economy of the category. In the category, we can reason about rights, obligations, laws and principles, and yet ethics may never happen – actual faces starve, die, are humiliated and scorned as they circulate in the economy of our categories. They fall through the cracks of our debates, arguments and counterarguments, and yet we feel justified – we have our reasons; it was the right thing to do after all. This desire to call forth, to render present what ‘is’, has always been at the heart of western thought – the project of being as defined by Heidegger. Truth as unconcealment (alethia) of what ‘is’. In the gaze of consciousness, the concealed (lethia) is made present (alethia). The task of western consciousness, of Philosophy with a big ‘P’, is to draw the Other, the strange, always at the edges, into the light of the present – to expand the horizon of consciousness is its calling. In the expanding horizon of consciousness, the strange, the Other, is a ‘not-yet’, waiting to be domesticated by the revealing gaze of intentionality. Hitherto, the singular has always disturbed the systems of philosophy. As Caputo (1993: 73) suggests: The individual, according to the most classical axiomatic, is ineffable (individuum ineffable est). That is to announce with admirable rigor a breach in the surface of philosophy. It formulates a principle for what falls outside principles, a covering law for what law can not cover, for a kind of out-law. It announces with all desirable clarity that the individual is both necessary and impossible . . . For to understand metaphysics, which takes itself to be the science of what is real, one must understand that the only thing that is real, the individual – sola individua existunt – is the one thing of which it cannot speak.

However, by saying that the singular is ineffable we have already said too much. We have already brought it into our system of thought. We now have a location for it. It no longer disturbs us, or surprises us. In some small but significant way, we have already domesticated it. This is the impos-

266

sibility we face, this very face, here now, before me. It is wholly Other, in a way that never allows me to settle down into my system of thought. If this is so, how can the Other disturb me without becoming content of consciousness? Levinas uses the familiar event of a doorbell ringing to disturb my work, my thoughts, but when I open the door, there is nobody there. Was there nobody there? Did I imagine it? I have no memory, I cannot recall. The absolutely other – the infinity – does not move in the temporal horizon of being. Its presence ‘does not simply lead to the past but is the very passing toward a past more remote than any past and any future which still are set in my [ego] time . . .’ (Levinas 1996a: 63). Just when I settle back into my thoughts the doorbell rings again, and again and again – but there is never some body there. The subject is affected without the source of the affection becoming a theme of re-presentation. The term obsession designates this relation, which is irreducible to consciousness. ‘Obsession traverses consciousness contrariwise, inscribing itself there as something foreign, as disequilibrium, as delirium, undoing thematization, eluding principle, origin and will, all of which are affirmed in every gleam of consciousness’ (Levinas 1996c: 80– 81). It is this relationship of incessantly there but never present that Levinas calls proximity, the relationship with the absolute stranger. Anarchically, proximity is a relationship with a singularity, without the mediation of any principle or ideality. It is the summoning of myself by the other (autrui), it is a responsibility toward those whom we do not even know. The relation of proximity does not amount to any modality of distance or geometrical contiguity, nor to the simple ‘representation’ of the neighbour. It is already a summons of extreme exigency, an obligation which is anachronistically prior to every engagement. An anteriority that is older than the a priori. (Levinas 1996c: 81, italics in the original)

This proximity, this very nearness that is never there and that escapes my themes and yet always disturbs me, prevents me from settling down in my thoughts, is signified in the face of the other. r 2007 The Author Journal compilation r 2007 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

Business Ethics: A European Review Volume 16 Number 3 July 2007

The face of the other is not merely the empirical face, and yet the empirical face does serve as a signifier that signifies the always already ineffable of the singular confronting me. It is the placeholder that never settles down in any ‘place’ yet ceaselessly reminds me that ‘I’ have already taken its ‘place’. ‘The proximity of the other is the face’s meaning’, writes Levinas (1996c: 82). As a face, the other becomes my neighbour – the one closest to me that demands my attention. Her face calls me, solicits me and in so doing recalls my responsibility. The moment I catch a glimpse of her face, ‘I’ become questioned. Am I not occupying her place in the sun? Her face keeps me hostage in its total uncoveredness and nakedness, in the defencelessness of her eyes, the straightforwardness and absolute frankness of her gaze. Her face resists me, not as a power that confronts me, but as a measure that puts me into question, immediately and absolutely. The indictment of the ego is ‘produced when I incline myself not before the facts, but before the other. In her face the other appears to me not as an obstacle, nor as a menace I evaluate, but as what measures me. For me to feel myself unjust I must measure myself against infinity’ (Levinas 1996b: 58). I stand accused, always already accused. Without having done anything, I have always been accused. I must respond, not out of my choosing but before my freedom, before my choosing. All I can say is ‘I’ – ‘I’ as in ‘I am guilty’, ‘I am the murderer’ and ‘I am responsible’. I am for the other. This taking up of my responsibility Levinas calls substitution. However, this taking up is not an act; it is rather an absolute passivity. In resolving not to be, ‘subjectivity undoes essence by substituting itself for the other’. I become a subject in the fullest sense of the word. My uniqueness, my autonomy, is the fact that no one can answer for me. Morality is not a moral choice by a free self-certain ego. It is rather in the encounter with the infinitely other that I can become questioned, I recall my guilt and accept (by absolute passivity) my responsibility, be subject for the other – not an I-am but an I-amfor-the-other, as suggested above. My subjectivity always already refers to the Other as its source, its moral force. As Cohen (1986: 5) argues: r 2007 The Author Journal compilation r 2007 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

Moral force cannot be reduced to cognitive cogency, to acts of consciousness or will. One can always refuse its claim . . . and the capacity to rationalise such refusal is certainly without limit. Ethical necessity lies in a different sort of refusal, a refusal of concepts. It lies in the prethematic demands that are necessarily lost in the elaboration of themes. Ethical necessity lies in the social obligation prior to thematic thought, in the disturbance suffered by thematic thought . . . This is not because ethics makes some truths better and others worse, but because it disrupts the entire project of knowing with a higher call, a more severe ‘condition’: responsibility.

If this is true, if the force of morality is in proximity of the face of the other, what about all other Others already implied in the very face before me? Surely, I am also an Other for others? Is there not a limit to my being hostage for the Other? These questions need to be addressed. This is the purpose of the next section.

Symmetry and singular justice Levinas (1991 [1974]: 158) argues that we cannot speak of the Other without immediately and simultaneously speaking of all Others. The face of the Other obsesses me both in its refusal to be contained (rendered equal) and its recalling of the always already equal claim of all Others weighing down on me in this particular face before me. In the face of the Other is signified always and already the face of all other Others – the ‘third’ in Levinas’s terminology. In the words of Critchley (1999: 226–7): Thus my ethical relation to the Other is an unequal, asymmetrical relation to a height that cannot be comprehended, but which, at the same time, opens onto a relation to the third and to humanity as a whole – that is, to a symmetrical community of equals. This simultaneity of ethics and politics gives a doubling quality to all discourse . . . the community has a double structure; it is a community of equals which is at the same time based on the inegalitarian moment of the ethical relation.

It is exactly this simultaneous presence of the Other and all other Others that gives birth to the

267

Business Ethics: A European Review Volume 16 Number 3 July 2007

question of justice. The urgency of justice is an urgency borne out of the radical asymmetry of every ethical relation. Without such a radical asymmetry the claim of the Other can always in principle become determined and codified into a calculation, justice as a calculation and distribution. Thus, justice has its standard, its force, in the proximity of the face of the Other. As Levinas (1991 [1994]: 159) asserts: ‘justice remains justice only, in a society where there is no distinction between those close and those far off, but in which there also remains the impossibility of passing by the closest. The equality of all is born by my inequality, the surplus of my duties over my rights. The forgetting of self moves justice’ (emphasis added). This formulation of justice by Levinas highlights the tension, one could almost say a profound ‘paradox’, in Levinas’s notion of justice. There ought to be ‘no distinction between those close and those far off’ yet at the same time it ought to remain ‘impossible to pass by the closest’. This fundamental and necessary tension is what Critchley termed above the ‘double structure’ of community: living with ‘the law’ and ‘the face of the Other’ at the same time. It is exactly this paradoxical tension that Derrida (1992) addresses in his paper ‘Force of law: the mystical foundation of authority’, to which I will now turn. In his essay, Derrida (1992) distinguishes between the law (droit) – we could also add policy or any other explicit rules for directing conduct and for settling disputes – and justice (juste). Law, for Derrida, is the positive structures that make up the judicial systems of one sort or another, by virtue of which actions are said to be legal, legitimate, or properly authorized (Caputo 1997: 130). Derrida argues that the law – to be law – must be enforceable; it must have some force. This connection between law and force is easily recognizable in our everyday speech when we use the phrase ‘the force of the law’ or ‘can we enforce this law?’ But where does this force come from? What authority or foundation provides this basis for law to have force? Derrida responds to this question by suggesting that the origin of the authority of the law, which gives it its force, is unfounded. No matter how detailed we do our analysis, whether we analyse the reasons,

268

the debates, the arguments, the institutions, the decision processes, the power structures, the regimes of truth (in Foucault’s language) and so forth, we will not discover the ultimate source or foundation that guarantees this authority, gives it its force. Derrida (1992: 13) concludes: ‘Its very moment of foundation or institution . . . the operation that amounts to founding, inaugurating, justifying law (droit), making law, would consist of a coup de force, of a performative and therefore interpretative violence that in itself is neither just nor unjust and that no previous law with its founding anterior moment could guarantee or contradict or invalidate’. Thus, law is constructed through a performative act that is always in some form or another self-authorizing. One could respond with disappointment, ‘what now?’ Are we now in an endless sea of nihilism? No, not so. Rather, its unfoundedness is simultaneously the opening up of the possibility for ‘salvation’ – as constructed it is always in principle deconstructable. This deconstructable nature of the law creates the space, the possibility for justice. If law had an ultimate foundation then the face of the Other, the singular, would always be consumable by this force. The face would lose its authority. Note, however, that the authority of the face is not to suggest or demand but rather to question, to disturb, to obsess, the auto-authority of the law. Singular justice – as I will call it2 – is this possibility of a space opening up between the authority of the law, which it has even if we cannot find it as such, and the incessant questioning and disturbing of this authority by the singular naked face of the Other before me ‘here and now’. We can visualize singular justice as a Mo¨bius strip. When you are on the inside you are also immediately and simultaneously on the outside. It is rather appropriately like the infinite sign ‘1’, as it is infinite. Whenever we follow its trajectory, we always tend to end up on the other side of where we thought we were or where we wanted to be. We need the law (droit) to give our judgement ‘force’, and yet when we face the other, in its singularity, it shatters the law, making the law seem perverse, like a caricature devoid of reality and relevance. However, when we then suspend the law to deal with this singular, before r 2007 The Author Journal compilation r 2007 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

Business Ethics: A European Review Volume 16 Number 3 July 2007

me ‘here and now’, we become aware, in rather an acute way, that every other Other, simultaneously present in the face of this Other before me, is also an Other singular whose claim is equally legitimate. Thus, we are thrown back onto the law, the equality of every possible Other before the law. It is impossible. Let me give an example to make clearer the simultaneity of ethics and justice. Let us imagine that we are in the room of our local doctor with our partner to hear the outcome of some tests conducted on tissue taken from a suspicious growth. The doctor informs us that the tests were unfortunately positive. It is a cancerous growth that is potentially life threatening. Furthermore, although it is operable, he cannot perform the operation because the rules (law – droit) for allocating resources make it a lower priority than other conditions (such as AIDS treatment, and neo-natal care) and these have already drained the available resources. At this moment, here and now, sitting before this doctor, these rules seem like a caricature devoid of reality and relevance. ‘Doctor, are you saying that my partner might die because the ‘‘rules’’ for resource allocation do not favour her condition?’ This is certainly perverse, absolutely irrelevant. It is my partner, ‘this person sitting before you that we are talking about; not some general instance in the logic of the rules’. Yet, as the initial rage subsides, we realize that every other Other, simultaneously present in this moment of disappointment, is also a singular – a ‘wife’, ‘baby’, ‘brother’, a face – with an equally legitimate claim. ‘What about my son, my daughter, my partner?’ We are thrown back onto the law. It is impossible. How can we do singular justice? To answer this question, I want to turn to Derrida again. In the work of Derrida, we see a subtle rearticulation of Levinas’s ethics.3 What Derrida does, and Levinas did not do as explicitly, is to suggest how the impossibility between ethics and justice – what I refer to as singular justice – might play itself out in the institutions of everyday life.

The aporia of singular justice With Derrida I will argue that this impossible possibility of singular justice is what makes ethics r 2007 The Author Journal compilation r 2007 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

a serious matter. It is an impossibility we need to face again and again for ethics to happen in the flow of everyday life. It is possible as we do find ourselves in it all the time, and yet it is impossible because it always already escapes our ability to resolve it, to solve it, ‘once and for all’. In the midst of this impossible possibility, we experience the aporia (a profound, even mystical, puzzle) of singular justice. When Derrida uses the term impossible he uses it as a term of art. It is not the logical opposite of possible. The possible is for Derrida the ‘future present’ – a possibility that can become actualized with hard work and maybe a bit of luck. On the other hand, the impossible is that which overflows all future possibilities, always already reaching to a ‘beyond’ that will never be a present, a ‘not yet’ that will never come – yet calls us with the utmost of urgency. To ‘desire the impossible is to strain against the constraints of the foreseeable and possible, to open the horizon of possibility to what it cannot [and never will] foresee or foretell’ (Caputo 1997: 133). According to Derrida, we simultaneously experience three aporia as we find ourselves in the impossible possibility of singular justice (Derrida 1992: 22). First aporia: the suspension of the law and the fresh judgement. Conformity to the law does not ensure justice; it only ensures legality. Singular justice requires that the law be reinvented for every case. Derrida (1992: 23) argues: to be just, the decision of a judge, for example, must not only follow a rule of law or a general law but must also assume it, approve it, confirm its value, by a reinstituting act of interpretation, as if ultimately nothing previously existed of the law, as if the judge himself invented the law in every case. No exercise of justice as law can be just [singular justice] unless there is a ‘fresh judgement’.

The requirements of the law must somehow be stretched to cover the singular without turning the singular into a case or an instance (which would be legal but not just) and without ignoring the law (which would be ethical but not just). Singular justice is found, if it is found at all, caught up between the ‘blind and universal law [justice] and the singularity of the situation before us [ethics]’.

269

Business Ethics: A European Review Volume 16 Number 3 July 2007

Second aporia: the ghost of undecidability. Undecidability is not the opposite of decidability but rather the opposite of ‘calculably, programmability, formalizability’ and the like. It is not merely being trapped in the tension between two equally relevant rules, thereby being paralysed ‘like a deer caught in a headlight’. A decision that did not go through the ‘ordeal of the undecidable’ is not a decision – it is a calculation. It may be legal but it would not be just. But more than this, undecidability is never resolved, never passed over. It is there before, during and after the decision has been made. Undecidability ‘remains caught, lodged, at least as a ghost – but an essential ghost – in every decision, in every event of decision. Its ghostliness deconstructs from within any assurance of presence, any certitude or any supposed criteriology that would assure us of the justice of a decision, in truth of the very event of a decision’ (Derrida 1992: 25). Singular justice happens, if it happens, only in the singular moment of the decision. The ‘warm glow of [singular] justice never settles over the law, the rule, the universal, [as] the ‘‘maxim’’ that can be drawn from this singular ‘‘event’’, or still less over the person deciding, who can never say ‘‘I am just’’’ (Caputo 1997: 138). Singular justice has to be invented and reinvented from decision to decision, decisions that sit uneasy, unable to settle down into the certainty of a precedent, a potential rule, or even a heuristic. Rather, continually disturbed by the radical singularity of the moment of decision – that is the ghost of undecidability that always remains to haunt any pretence to certainty of the law. Third aporia: urgency. Singular justice is always required here and now, in this singular situation. It cannot wait for more information, for all the facts to come in. A ‘just decision is always required immediately’ (Derrida 1992: 26). I may have time to reflect, gather information and deliberate alternatives, and yet the moment of decision always ‘marks the interruption of the juridico- or ethico- or politico-cognitive deliberation that precedes it, that must precede it’. The instant of decision, as Kierkegaard reminded us, is madness. However ‘much time is expended in deliberation, a [singular] just decision would

270

always demand action in a ‘‘finite moment of urgency and precipitation,’’ and would always be ‘‘structurally finite’’ . . .’ (Caputo 1997: 138). Our deliberations seem not to prepare us for the moment, the immediacy, of having to leap, here and now. The singular ‘here and now’ makes all our deliberation suddenly seem irrelevant and unrelated, and yet we must decide ‘here and now’. The aporia of suspension, undecidability and urgency is the ‘stuff’ of singular justice. It is the stuff of ethical action of moral conduct. Singular justice is an impossible possibility. Ethics is not easy (it never was) and it is getting more difficult as more and more faces ‘face’ us in our shrinking world. Ethical theory is not going to solve this for us. We must argue, we must debate, we must calculate, justice – all other Others – demands this of us. However, such debating and calculating is always already disturbed, in some fundamental way, by the urgency of the radically singular always on the ‘outside’ of our reasons, logic and categories. Singular justice is impossible but is all we have. How might we practise the aporia of suspension, undecidability and urgency that singular justice demands of us?

The vocation of singular justice: ‘faceing’ the aporia Singular justice is an infinite vocation. It is a calling as the Latin root vocaˆtioˆ suggests. But it is not just a general calling to whoever is available or ready to answer. A vocation is precisely a ‘vocation’ because it is always and already my calling. The calling immediately and simultaneously designates the one being called – me. That is why vocaˆtioˆ was used in Latin to refer to a citing or summons before a court or a binding invitation to an event such as a dinner – it refers to a particular singular being summoned or invited. The calling of the Other, more precisely the calling into question of me by the proximity of the Other, is an ‘acceptance of a vocation to which I alone can respond or again, the power to respond to it when called. To be free is only to do what nobody else can do in my place’ (Levinas as quoted by Fabio Ciaramelli 1991: 88, emphasis r 2007 The Author Journal compilation r 2007 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

Business Ethics: A European Review Volume 16 Number 3 July 2007

added). My singularity has its origin in the fact that nobody else can take up my ‘calling’ here and now. In being hostage, in facing the aporia of singular justice, I become the already chosen me, which is an already for-the-Other. The uniqueness of me, the source of my calling, is that it is ‘I and no one else, who is a hostage for the others. In substitution my being that belongs to me and not to another is undone, and it is through this substitution that I am not ‘‘‘another’’, but me . . . . I am unique and chosen; the election is in the subjection’ (Levinas 1991 [1974]: 126–127, emphasis added). The vocation of singular justice calls me, summons me, not to activity – it is not a call to action – but rather it is a calling into question of the self-certainty of the self. It is a calling into question that leaves the self radically paralysed; a radical passivity, in which the self has no currency whatsoever – except as a substitute, as a for-theOther. It is only in this substitution, in the grip of this radical passivity, that we can approach the aporia of singular justice. Indeed, the aporia of singular justice are constantly threatened by the possibility of action in which the self would assert itself rather than being a substitute for the Other. This is why the practice of the aporia only makes sense if the one doing it finds herself in the proximity of the Other. The impossible possibility of the aporia of singular justice is only to be found in the proximity of the Other. This is my calling, my vocation. How might this calling work itself out in the flow of everyday life? In the next section, I will attempt to illustrate how singular justice might emerge in the concrete ethics of everyday (business) life. In considering this ‘example’ we must be careful to note that we are not applying Levinas to a case. To apply Levinas would be to turn Levinas’s ethics into a theory or abstraction that would need to be applied to the instance – in other words, it would enter into the economy of the category and the instance to be covered by the category. It is exactly these totalizing attempts by Moral Philosophy that Levinas is criticizing. Levinas’s ethics cannot solve cases. It can only open up the possibility (and it always remains a very fragile possibility) that we might become disturbed by r 2007 The Author Journal compilation r 2007 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

the face of the Other and take up our calling, our singular vocation.

Singular justice and the face of the software pirate The purpose of intellectual property law, so it is argued, is to balance the property rights of the creators (to derive fair benefit from their creations) and access rights of society (to have reasonable access to such goods) (Hettinger 1989). In recent years, however, this ‘balancing’ has gone steadfastly in the direction of disproportionately securing the rights of the creators, as argued by Lipinski & Britz (2000) – a trend they term ‘proprietarianism’. The aggressiveness of this trend is reflected in the Global Piracy Report (SIIA 2000: 3–4) of the Software and Information Industry Association (SIIA). In this report they claim that: An effective intellectual property system is one that adequately protects its nation’s software creations and inventions. First and foremost, each nation must enact appropriate laws. ‘Appropriate,’ in this context, means the laws should acknowledge the rights of creators and owners of computer software, be comprehensive and leave no doubt as to what rights and remedies are granted in the law. . . . Finally, the public should be educated and understand the protections afforded to computer programs under copyright and other intellectual property laws.

It is interesting and informative that the report does not make any mention whatsoever that ‘appropriate’ laws should also ensure reasonable access to society to these goods or that the public should be ‘educated’ to know their rights of access. Unfortunately the emerging legal framework in the USA – which is supposed to ensure equal protection of the rights of property and access – is being constructed in a context where there are massive power asymmetries between the parties trying to secure these rights. In such a context, the SIIA’s view and the current disproportionate protection of property rights in the USA is not surprising. It is also not surprising that the SIIA is actively working

271

Business Ethics: A European Review Volume 16 Number 3 July 2007

with officials from the Office of the U.S. Trade Representatives and other executive branch and congressional officials to correct deficiencies in legal regimes and enforcement [of other countries] and directly lobbies foreign governments and international organizations for improvement in the intellectual property protections afforded computer software . . . [to] at least as high as that required by the Agreement on Trade-Related Aspects of Intellectual Property Rights (TRIPs) or, if applicable, at higher levels set by multilateral and bilateral agreements. (SIIA 2000: 11–12, emphasis added)

At the end of the SIIA piracy report, it is claimed that ‘as long as software piracy remains, there will be fewer jobs, less research and development, increased costs and lower standards of living’ (21). Given that the vast majority of software is produced in the United States by about 1000 companies,4 and the huge profits made by these companies, it is unlikely that this statement could be true. In fact, it is more likely that the aggressive push for property rights, and the associated attempts to expand this propertycentred legal framework to other countries with ‘deficient’ legal frameworks, would result in access being denied to those who one might argue need it most. It is to such a singular case5 that I now want to turn. Peter Mutzi is a Maths teacher in a rural secondary school about 50 miles from Karonga. Karonga is one of the major towns in the sparsely populated north of Malawi. Peter succeeded in negotiating with a development agency for access to a standalone PC, printer and some computer stationery. He intends to start an after-school workshop where children can learn computer skills. He believes such skills will enable them to gain access to better jobs when they move inevitably to the capital Lilongwe or the commercial centre Blantyre. Unfortunately, when the computer arrived it was only loaded with a Windows 98 operating system. No application software was included. Peter was keen to teach the students word-processing, spreadsheets, graphics and databases. While at Bunda College of Agriculture, which is part of the University of Malawi, he had an opportunity to use Microsoft

272

Office. The limited availability of computers at the university prevented him from gaining a high level of proficiency. Nevertheless, these skills, although limited, were considered to be very valuable by his employer and are also highly sought after in the commercial centres. He was determined to get a copy of Microsoft Office for the school computer. This would also allow him to increase his knowledge of the MS Office applications. With these increased skills, he could contribute to the management of the school and be a more effective tutor for the children. He did some research and discovered the following:  A full version of Microsoft Office would cost US$383. With postage and packaging it would increase to US$405, as it would have to be imported.  There is a person, John Bisengo, in Lilongwe who sells CD-ROMs with the full version of MS Office for US$5. These copies can only be bought in person and do not include any documentation or support. The trip to Lilongwe would cost about US$3. Peter would have to pay for the software himself, as the school does not have any budget available for such expenditure. He also does not want to go back to the development agency for help as he feels the school should contribute its own share in getting the system up and running. His gross annual salary is US$300. After considering the options, it is evident that there is no alternative for him. He will have to travel to Lilongwe to buy the ‘pirate’ CD-ROM for US$5. Was Peter doing the wrong thing in opting to buy the pirate copy? In the view of the SIIA, John and Peter are pirates who should be prosecuted for their actions; the law is the law, without exception. The universality of the law, the fact we are equal before it, is exactly what gives it its force. However, should we not consider the particular situation in developing countries and the singular situation of Peter? The SIIA responds: Unfortunately, in many countries with developing economies, demand for software is being met by piracy – not by publishers. American software

r 2007 The Author Journal compilation r 2007 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

Business Ethics: A European Review Volume 16 Number 3 July 2007

publishers are unable to compete with counterfeit operations that duplicate their programs and distribute them directly to consumers on street corners and shops throughout the world at prices often as low as $2. . . . Although some argue that lower levels of personal income justify software piracy, this is misleading. In most developing countries, computer software is only used by a relatively small group of individuals and organizations affluent enough to purchase computers, not by the average citizen. More significantly, if individuals and organizations can afford to buy computer hardware, why shouldn’t they be expected to purchase legitimate copies of software to run on that hardware? Arguments citing the industry’s infancy, fragility or strategic importance are secondary, at best, because governmental initiatives in support of a local software industry so often lead to protectionism, lack of competition and technological stagnation. Software piracy prevents natural allocation of resources in an efficient manner and calls for targeted governmental intervention. (SIIA 2000: 15)

Let us consider this argument. First, they argue that selling the software at $2 does not allow for fair competition, and obviously they are right. However, if we consider the problem from the other side then a different picture emerges. What is the cost to Peter? In the USA, an average teacher’s salary could be taken as approximately $40,000/year. If a copy of MS Office costs $383 at retail price (which would presumably be the fair competitive price for the SIIA) then the cost of the MS office to a teacher in the United States as percentage of annual income would be 0.96%. If Peter also pays 0.96% of his annual salary, then an equivalent cost for him would be $2.87. If we take it from the point of view of relative cost to the individual then $2 does not seem as outrageous as they suggest. We could also do the calculation using per capita gross national product (GNP). US per capita GNP is $29,240. MS Office as percentage of per capita GNP is 1.31%. If we take 1.31% of Malawian per capita GNP – which is $551 – then a fair cost would be $7.22. They proceed to argue that ‘if individuals and organizations can afford to buy computer hardware, why shouldn’t they be expected to purchase r 2007 The Author Journal compilation r 2007 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

legitimate copies of software to run on that hardware?’ Again, it is a very legitimate (legally correct) claim. However, as all information technology equipment and software are imported it must be paid for in US dollars. When you have a currency that is continually devaluing – in 1998 25 Malawi Kwacha (MK) 5 US$1; in 2001 79.5MK 5 US$1 – and with an inflation rate of 35%, any import becomes very expensive indeed. Additionally, Malawi is a country where between 60% and 65% of the population live below the poverty line (NSOM 2005). This means they do not have the $49 a year or 14 cents a day to acquire the basic needs to sustain themselves. It is obvious that in such a context the ‘piracy’ of software is a very attractive option indeed – if not the only option. Nevertheless, the SIIA is legally right; it is illegal to pirate software. These rights are accorded them through the Berne Convention (1971) and TRIPS (1994) agreements, even if we might argue that these conventions and agreements are unjust. They can legally insist that these rights be honoured. Indeed, they may point to Kant’s categorical imperative and claim that most people would suggest that the actions of Peter and John are wrong because no reasonable person would want it to become a universal law, i.e. to be a maxim for everybody who cannot afford to pay the full price. Yet, in the face of the singular, Peter in Malawi, wanting to get a better deal for his students, their claims seem perverse, even outrageous. Will the face of Peter, disturb the self-evidentness of the law? If we consider the singular case of Peter the argument quoted above seems perverse, especially the last sentence: ‘Software piracy prevents natural allocation of resources in an efficient manner and calls for targeted governmental intervention.’ What shall we say? Can justice become singular? First, we have to suspend the certainty of the law and make a fresh judgement. We have to say that the Berne Convention and other associate legal frameworks are legally right – it is the law even if we think it is fundamentally flawed – and it demands to be implemented by all without exception. That is what makes laws forceful; they apply (indeed should apply) to all equally. It would be legally right to ask Peter to pay more than his annual salary to buy this software, but

273

Business Ethics: A European Review Volume 16 Number 3 July 2007

would it be just? Would it be doing singular justice? However, maybe, just maybe (as we say this with great uncertainty), it would be doing singular justice to ask him to pay $5 for the software (with manuals included). The law rightly demands payment, that the rights of the other be honoured. Now the SIIA would object and say that they would not be able to make their (un)reasonable profit at that price, and they are legally right – but would they be doing singular justice? They may invoke a consequentialist argument. They may argue that they have a right to earn a reasonable profit from their labour and that if this were not the case, then programmers would not have the incentive to produce software, which would end up being bad for everybody. This is a classical consequentialist defence of intellectual property rights (see Kimppa 2004). However, if so few people use software in developing countries, as they claim, it may not be a problem. Nevertheless, we are not suggesting that all persons in developing countries should be paying $5. Singular justice has to do with the singular, with the ‘here and now’ before us. It is not about creating policy or legal precedents. We are not making a policy statement. We are only saying maybe it would be just and fair to ask Peter to pay $5 for the software. He must pay (something); this is the legitimate requirement of the law. We should note, however, that in claiming that it might be just and fair for Peter to pay $5 we are not simply ‘solving’ the ethical aporia by turning Peter into an exception. Being disturbed by the Other is not simply giving way to exceptionalism. Indeed, Peter is exceptional but so are many other Others not now present. Justice demands that we make ‘no distinction between those close and those far off, but in which there also remains the impossibility of passing by the closest’. We are caught, always and already caught, in the aporia of undecidability. However, maybe the perversity of the claim of the law, in the face of Peter, will make the law (and the SIIA) less certain of itself, of its assumed legitimacy – this is the concern of singular justice. Maybe Peter’s singular claim will cast doubt on the seemingly self-evidentness of their property claims and expose the (necessary) violence of the law.

274

However, what about policy? Does singular justice not concern itself with policy then? It does. Singular justice is the ‘what about?’ or ‘what if?’ that is simultaneously present in every positive and certain statement in the policy – destabilizing it, filling it with doubt. It is the host of silenced voices covered over, violently suppressed, by the dominant interpretation – waiting to say, not forcefully, but with a whisper, ‘what about us?’. It is these simultaneously present singulars in every positive policy statement that may, just maybe, make it pause . . . long enough . . . to see the face of the singular before it ‘here and now’. We must argue, debate, construct policy, regulation and the law; justice demands this of us. Nevertheless, we must equally and simultaneously accept that the policy, regulation and law will need to be suspended and reinvented every time it faces the singular Other that it is supposed to cover. Singular justice requires that every application of the policy be a fresh judgement, as if every case is unprecedented, without simply turning every singular into an exception. This is the impossible possibility of singular justice.

Some concluding comments Levinas teaches us that ethics cannot be solved. To solve ethics (as ethical theory suggests), we will need to turn the singular other(s) into ethical categories of the same – for example as instances in our moral categories of ‘consequences’, ‘values’, ‘virtues’, ‘rights’, etc. This supposed solution, in its ‘solving’, is violent. For it to be possible, the infinitely singular must be forced into the limits of the category. That which is incomparable must become (with violent force) comparable – your rights against my rights, the consequences for the group against the consequences for the individual and so forth. Unfortunately, this violence is frequently necessary, often rightly demanded from us. However, what is not necessary is the forgetting (or denial) of the violence of our supposed ‘solution’ – the forgetting of the face in the economy of the category, or worse, the very forgetting of our forgetting. We can and must propose policy, law and moral theory. However, in r 2007 The Author Journal compilation r 2007 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

Business Ethics: A European Review Volume 16 Number 3 July 2007

making policy, in executing the rule of law, we must also remain disturbed by the simultaneously present calling of the Other. The singular in our categories must haunt us; obsess us with the nakedness of their stare. They must shatter the certainty of our moral calculations – they must force us to ask always, again and again, ‘yes, but what about her, or him, or them?’. How will we do singular justice in organizations? We know how to carry out moral calculations, to make policies, consider their consequences, to be fair – ethical theory teaches us this. However, we do not often get shaken and disturbed by the singular. The voice of the other often disappears in our organizing technologies of structures, positions, responsibilities, procedures, policies, etc. How then will we encounter the Other in the midst of the captivating flow of everyday life where we are desperately struggling ‘just to get the job done’? Obviously, we cannot ‘solve’ ethics but we can allow ethical practice to become disturbed, to fill it with profound doubt, push it back to the uncertainty of the aporia, to not allow it to become settled in any way whatsoever. I would suggest – with a lot of trepidation that it might be seen as principles or rules – that we might adopt the following impossible possible practices of singular justice. a. Suspension through facing: We must always allow the singulars to speak, to show their faces – although not through representation. They must speak directly, by facing, to those who make the policy, those who do the moral calculation. Levinas suggests that the face solicits us through its expression. The event proper to expression consists in ‘bearing witness to oneself, and guaranteeing this witness. This attestation of oneself is possible only as a face, that is, as speech’ (Levinas 1967: 201). For these policy makers to become uncertain, they must face the possibility of hearing the actual voices of those affected by their judgements. For example, we saw in the Truth and Reconciliation Commission in South Africa (and Northern Ireland) that if enemies face each other and speak, the self-evidentness of the category ‘enemy’ explodes. In their speaking, we must r 2007 The Author Journal compilation r 2007 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

allow the victims to explode the evidence of the law, the theory and the answer. b. Undecidability and the possibility for appeal: We must acknowledge the undecidability of our impossible moral dilemmas by always leaving open the possibility for appeal. However, in appealing, the singular is not supposed to become simply an exception. Rather, in the appeal the exceptionality and the unprecedentedness of each singular must be allowed to continually overturn the ‘decided’ into the undecided – to obsess and disturb the ‘decided’ in its certainty. c. Urgency and the here and now: There is no better time for singular justice than ‘here and now’ by taking up our responsibility to those facing us. We must not allow the displacement of the urgency that singular justice demands, the urgency of the face facing me (or us) here and now. ‘Outside’ of the urgency of the here and now the category can easily return to cover over the singular. In time, memory fades, the echo of the Other already recalling my responsibility falls silent. The disturbing voice of the face that now unsettles me can be forgotten so easily. It is only in facing the singular without the certainty of the law or the theory that singular justice might just happen. For singular justice to happen – if it happens at all – we must find ourselves entangled in its impossible possibility, and work it out for ourselves. It is our calling alone, again and again, here and now. This is the nature of morality in everyday life; it is impossible and very frail. Nevertheless, it is all we have.

Notes 1. The Enron ethical code declared that: ‘Employees of ENRON Corp., its subsidiaries, and its affiliated companies (collectively called the ‘Company’) are charged with conducting their business affairs in accordance with the highest ethical standards. An employee shall not conduct himself or herself in a manner, which directly or indirectly would be detrimental to the best interests of the Company or in a manner, which would bring to

275

Business Ethics: A European Review Volume 16 Number 3 July 2007

2.

3.

4.

5.

the employee financial gain separately derived as a direct consequence of his or her employment with the Company. Moral as well as legal obligations will be fulfilled openly, promptly, and in a manner which will reflect pride on the Company’s name’. I follow Edgoose (1997) in using the term ‘singular justice’ (although he uses ‘caring justice’) to try and retain some elements of Levinas’s notion of justice – which could be said to be more like Derrida’s concept of law (droit), but not quite – and Derrida’s notion of justice, which could be said to be more like Levinas’s notion of ethics, but not quite. Derrida comments on this relation of terms but also warns against taking it too far, and so I will not (see Derrida 1992: 22). Refer to Plant (2003) for a discussion of the relationship between the work of Levinas and Derrida. Plant argues that Derrida’s work, especially his work on hospitality, is fundamentally Levinasian. The SIIA represents approximately 1000 companies that represent 85% of US revenue for packaged and online software. Although the personal details of this case are fictional, the quantitative data that it is based upon are actual data taken from a variety of sources.

References ‘Berne Convention for the protection of literary and artistic works’, 1971. http://www.law.cornell.edu/ treaties/berne/overview.html (accessed 30 June 2006). Caputo, J.D. 1993. Against Ethics. Indianapolis, IN: Indiana University Press. Caputo, J.D. 1997. Deconstruction in a Nutshell. New York: Fordham University Press. Caputo, J.D. 2000. More Radical Hermeneutics: On Not Knowing Who We Are. Indianapolis, IN: Indiana University Press. Ciaramelli, F. 1991. ‘Ethical discourse between individuation and universality’. In Bernasconi, R. and Critchley, S. (Eds.), Re-reading Levinas: 83–105. Indianapolis, IN: Indiana University Press. Cohen, R.A. 1986. Face to Face with Levinas. New York: State University of New York Press. Critchley, S. 1999. The Ethics of Deconstruction: Derrida and Levinas. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.

276

Derrida, J. 1992. ‘Force of law: the mystical foundation of authority’. In Cornell, D., Rosenfeld, M. and Carlson, D.G. (Eds.), Deconstruction and the Possibility of Justice: 3–67. London: Routledge. Edgoose, J. 1997. ‘An ethics of hesitant learning: the caring justice of Levinas and Derrida’. In Philosophy of Education Yearbook, http://www.ed.uiuc.edu/ EPS/PES-Yearbook/97_docs/edgoose.html (accessed 30 June 2006). Hettinger, E. 1989. ‘Justifying intellectual property’. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 18:1, 31–52. Introna, L.D. 2001. ‘Virtuality and morality: on (not) being disturbed by the Other’. Philosophy in the Contemporary World, 8:1, 31–39. Introna, L.D. 2002. ‘On the (im)possibility of ethics in a mediated world’. Information and Organisation, 12, 71–84. Introna, L.D. 2003. ‘Workplace surveillance ‘‘is’’ unethical and unfair’. Surveillance and Society, 1:2, 210–216. Jones, C., Parker, M. and ten Bos, R. 2005. For Business Ethics. London: Routledge. Kant, I. 1946 [1785]. Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysics of Ethics. London: Longmans Green (translated by T. K. Abbott). Kimppa, K. 2004. ‘Consequentialist considerations of intellectual property rights in software and other digital media’. In Ethicomp 2004, Proceedings of the Seventh International Conference, Vol. 2: 483–496. Greece: University of the Agean. Levinas, E. 1967. Totality and Infinity: An Essay on Exteriority. Pittsburgh, PA: Duquesne University Press (translated by A. Lingis). Levinas, E. 1985. Ethics and Infinity. Pittsburgh, PA: Duquesne University Press. Levinas, E. 1989. ‘Ethics as first philosophy’. In Hand, S. (Ed.), The Levinas Reader: 75–87. Oxford: Blackwell. Levinas, E. 1991 [1974]. Otherwise than Being or Beyond Essence. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers. Levinas, E. 1996a. ‘Meaning and sense’. In Peperzak, A., Critchley, S. and Bernasconi, R. (Eds.), Emmanuel Levinas: Basic Philosophical Writings: 33–64. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press. Levinas, E. 1996b. ‘Philosophy and the idea of infinity’. In Lingis, A. (Ed.), Philosophical Papers: Emmanuel Levinas: 46–72. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press.

r 2007 The Author Journal compilation r 2007 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

Business Ethics: A European Review Volume 16 Number 3 July 2007

Levinas, E. 1996c. ‘Substitution’. In Peperzak, A., Critchley, S. and Bernasconi, R. (Eds.), Emmanuel Levinas: Basic Philosophical Writings: 79–95. Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press. Lipinski, T.A. and Britz, J.J. 2000. ‘Rethinking the ownership of information in the 21st century: ethical implications’. Ethics and Information Technology, 2:1, 49–71. National Statistical Office of Malawi (NSOM). 2005. http://www.nso.malawi.net/ (accessed 30 June 2006).

r 2007 The Author Journal compilation r 2007 Blackwell Publishing Ltd.

Plant, B. 2003. ‘Doing justice to the Derrida–Levinas connection: a response to Mark Dooley’. Philosophy and Social Criticism, 29:4, 427–450. SIIA. 2000. ‘The Global Piracy Report. Software and Information Industry Association’, http://www.siia. net/estore/GPR-00.pdf (accessed 30 June 2006). TRIPS 1994. ‘Agreement on trade-related aspects of intellectual property rights’, http://www.wto.org/ english/tratop_e/trips_e/t_agm0_e.htm (accessed 30 June 2006).

277

Singular justice and software piracy

Business Ethics: A European Review. Volume 16 Number 3 July ..... justice] unless there is a 'fresh judgement'. .... citing or summons before a court or a binding.

139KB Sizes 1 Downloads 289 Views

Recommend Documents

The Impact of Piracy on Prominent and Non-prominent Software ...
non-prominent software developers in markets based on a two-sided platform business. Consumer behavior is .... portance of software markets, which are organized as two-sided markets, software piracy in these markets is getting more ..... On file shar

piracy article.pdf
Page 1 of 1. Whoops! There was a problem loading this page. Retrying... Whoops! There was a problem previewing this document. Retrying... Download. Connect more apps... Try one of the apps below to open or edit this item. Main menu. Whoops! There was

piracy and book sales.pdf
There was a problem previewing this document. Retrying... Download. Connect more apps... Try one of the apps below to open or edit this item. piracy and book ...

Piracy and music sales: The effects of an anti-piracy law
May 6, 2014 - music are available. Before 2007, digital sales were negligible. All sales numbers are at the trade level, and they are adjusted for inflation and converted to 2009 SEK.18 The music data are provided by local branches of IFPI. IFPI memb

Download Audiology Business and Practice Management (Singular ...
Download Audiology Business and Practice. Management (Singular Publishing Group. Audiology Series) Full Books. Books detail. Title : Download Audiology ...

singular and plural nouns.pdf
There was a problem previewing this document. Retrying... Download. Connect more apps... Try one of the apps below to open or edit this item. singular and ...

end piracy, not liberty
harmful regulations on American businesses. Experts agree ... down pirate websites than asking US companies to censor the Web. Millions of ... to “not support.

singular and plural nouns.pdf
Plural Nouns: more than one. Singular Nouns: just one. Color and cut out sorting ... Page 2 of 2. Main menu. Displaying singular and plural nouns.pdf. Page 1 of ...

singular and plural nouns.pdf
singular and plural nouns.pdf. singular and plural nouns.pdf. Open. Extract. Open with. Sign In. Main menu. Displaying singular and plural nouns.pdf. Page 1 of ...

End Piracy, Not Liberty - PDFKUL.COM
Millions of Americans united in opposition to SOPA and PIPA.They told Congress not to censor the Web and not to cripple our innovation economy. 55. 110. 204. 113,000+ 115,000+. | JOIN THE GROUNDSWELL. +000'288. 3000,000+,. 1000,000+. ло. TERE. PIPA

Music Piracy and Neutralization: A Preliminary ...
The Internet and increased use of personal computer in recent years has provided a ... 1 Associate Professor, Department of Justice Administration, 208 Brigman Hall, ... operandi (e.g., CD burning, peer-top-peer networks, LAN file sharing, digital st

Singular e plural.pdf
Sign in. Loading… Whoops! There was a problem loading more pages. Retrying... Whoops! There was a problem previewing this document. Retrying.

stop online piracy act pdf
There was a problem previewing this document. Retrying... Download. Connect more apps... Try one of the apps below to open or edit this item. stop online ...

Singular perturbation and homogenization problems in ...
tale dell'equazione di Laplace, e introduciamo potenziali di strato e di volume periodici per l' ...... periodicity, but we can recover it by adding a suitable function.

Regular and singular Fermi-liquid fixed points in ...
Condens. Matter. 3, 9687 1991; P. D. Sacramento and P. Schlottmann, Phys. Rev. B 40, 431 1989. 6 P. Coleman and C. Pepin, Phys. Rev. B 68, 220405R 2003.

Singular and interactive effects of blowdown, salvage ...
+1 612 625 3733; fax: +1 612 625 5212. E-mail addresses: [email protected] ...... The impact of broadcast burning and fire severity on species composition and ...

Regular and singular Fermi-liquid fixed points in ...
30 T. Giamarchi, C. M. Varma, A. E. Ruckenstein, and P. Nozières,. Phys. Rev. Lett. 70, 3967 1993. 31 I. Affleck and A. Ludwig, Nucl. Phys. 360, 641 1991; I. Af-.

Largest and Smallest q-Singular Values - Semantic Scholar
smallest eigenvalue sn(A) of Gaussian random matrix A of size n × n has ... random matrices, Bernoulli matrices, covariance matrices, and general random ma-.

Largest and Smallest q-Singular Values - Semantic Scholar
... numbers of random matrices. PhD thesis, Mas- ... E-mail address: [email protected]. Department of ... MI 488244-. 1027. E-mail address: [email protected].