Polarity particles in an inquisitive discourse model∗ Donka Farkas UC Santa Cruz

Floris Roelofsen ILLC Amsterdam

Ljubljana, August 12, 2011

1

Introduction • Analysis of yes and no presented yesterday: – yes presupposes a unique highlighted alternative and confirms it – no presupposes one or more highlighted alternatives and rejects them all • Both yes and no are anaphoric in the sense that they presuppose one or more highlighted alternatives • We refer to these highlighted alternatives as antecedent possibilities • This analysis of yes and no accounts for: – The basic fact that yes and no cannot be used/interpreted in ‘out of the blue’ contexts – The distribution of yes and no in responses to various types of disjunctive questions and assertions • However, as soon as we consider responses to negative questions and assertions, the analysis does not make the right predictions anymore. • For instance, both yes and no can be used in a confirming response to a negative assertion (see Brasoveanu, Farkas, and Roelofsen, 2011, for experimental evidence): (1)

A: Sam didn’t call. B: Yes, he didn’t. / No, he didn’t.

• The account developed so far wrongly predicts that no cannot be used here. • More generally, it wrongly predicts that no can never be used in a confirming response. • Similarly, it wrongly predicts that yes can never be used in a reversing response: (2)

A: Sam didn’t call. B: Yes, he DID. / No, he DID.



A substantial part of the paper in progress that this handout is based on—the part that spells out the ‘inquisitive discourse model’ in detail—is left out here for reasons of time. Feedback of any kind will be very much appreciated. We are very grateful to Adrian Brasoveanu for fruitful collaboration on a closely related project.

1

• Our aims for today: – Extend the analysis of polarity particles developed so far to account for responses to negative questions1 and assertions, incorporating and further developing ideas from Farkas and Bruce (2010) and Farkas (2010, 2011) – Explore consequences for disjunctive questions and assertions (especially with negation) – Provide additional evidence for the account from languages other than English

2

Positive and negative possibilities • Consider the following contrast: (3)

Susan didn’t pass the exam. a. Yes, she didn’t pass. b. No, she didn’t pass.

(4)

Susan failed the exam. a. Yes, she failed. b. *No, she failed.

• (3) and (4) are entirely equivalent in the system developed so far: – They express exactly the same proposition – They highlight exactly the same possibility • Still, they do not license the same polarity particle responses. • This contrast can only be accounted for semantically if our notion of meaning is fine-grained enough—that is, if propositions have enough structure—to reflect the relevant difference between (3) and (4). • Basic idea: – Propositions are sets of possibilities, as before – Possibilities may be highlighted or not, as before – But now, possibilities may also be positive or negative – Negative possibilities are those that are introduced by negative clauses; all other possibilities are positive. – So: [[(3)]] consists of a negative possibility, while [[(4)]] consists of a positive possibility – Polarity phrases presuppose positive/negative antecedents, just like pronouns presuppose masculine/feminine antecedents – Polarity particles in English do double duty: ∗ They may signal whether the antecedent possibilities are confirmed or rejected ∗ or whether the antecedent possibilities are supposed to be positive or negative

2

[[ϕ]] [[ϕ]]H [[ϕ]]+ H

3

[[ϕ]]L [[ϕ]]− H

[[ϕ]]+ L

[[ϕ]]− L

Introducing negative possibilities • Notation – [[ϕ]] = the proposition expressed by ϕ – [[ϕ]]H = the possibilities in [[ϕ]] that are highlighted – [[ϕ]]L = the possibilities in [[ϕ]] that are not highlighted (‘lowlighted’) – [[ϕ]]+ H = the possibilities in [[ϕ]]H that are positive – [[ϕ]]− H = the possibilities in [[ϕ]]H that are negative – [[ϕ]]+ L = the possibilities in [[ϕ]]L that are positive – [[ϕ]]− L = the possibilities in [[ϕ]]L that are negative • Negative possibilities are introduced by sentential negation • The semantic contribution of sentential negation – [[not ϕ]]− H ={

S

[[ϕ]] }

− + – [[not ϕ]]+ H = [[not ϕ]]L = [[not ϕ]]L = ∅

In words: – [[not ϕ]] consists of a single negative highlighted possibility: the complement of

S

[[ϕ]]

• Examples – [[Susan failed the exam]]

consists of a single [H,+] possibility

– [[Susan did not pass the exam]]

consists of a single [H,−] possibility

– In both cases, the possibility involved consists of all worlds where Susan failed – However, in one case this possibility is positive, in the other it is negative 1

We will restrict our attention here to low negation polar questions (e.g., Did Peter not call? ). High negation polar questions (e.g., Didn’t Peter call? ) seem to pattern with positive polar questions.

3

4

PolP: absolute and relative polarity features • We will not directly specify the semantics of yes and no • Rather, we think of these polarity particles as realizing certain polarity features • Polarity features are hosted by a syntactic node which we will refer to as PolP • There are two relative polarity features: [same] and [reverse] • And there are also two absolute polarity features: [+] and [−] • PolP always hosts one relative polarity feature and one absolute polarity feature • Thus, in total there are four possible feature combinations in PolP: – [same,+] – [same,−] – [reverse,+] – [reverse,−] • To be specified: – The semantics of these four possible feature combinations in PolP – Feature realization rules: ∗ which particles can realize which features, and ∗ given a certain feature combination, which features are to be realized • Together, this will yield an account of the distribution and interpretation of yes and no

4.1

Interpretation of feature combinations in PolP

• [same,+] – presupposes that there is a unique [H,+] alternative on the Table2 – if this presupposition is met, it confirms the unique [H,+] alternative • [same,−] – presupposes that there is a unique [H,−] alternative on the Table – if this presupposition is met, it confirms the unique [H,−] alternative • [reverse,+] – presupposes that there is at least one [H,−] alternative on the Table – if this presupposition is met, it rejects all the [H,−] alternatives on the Table 2

We assume a discourse model that combines the basic architecture of (Farkas and Bruce, 2010) with inquisitive semantics. In this model, a discourse context includes a stack of propositions, representing the proposals under consideration. This stack of propositions is called the Table. For convenience, we refer to alternatives that are contained in the first proposition on the Table simply as ‘alternatives on the Table.’

4

• [reverse,−] – presupposes that there is at least one [H,+] alternative on the Table – if this presupposition is met, it rejects all the [H,+] alternatives on the Table • Thus, the different polarity phrases are characterized by: – the polarity of the antecedent possibilities (positive or negative) – the relationship between the antecedent and the response (confirming or reversing) – the polarity of the response (positive or negative) antecedent + − − +

4.2

relation confirming confirming reversing reversing

response + − + −

features [same,+] [same,−] [reverse,+] [reverse,−]

Realization rules

• Which particles can be used to realize which features? – [same] and [+] can be realized by yes – [reverse] and [−] can be realized by no • Thus, polarity particles in English do double duty – they are used to realize both absolute and relative polarity features • The use of one particle for [same] and [+], and another particle for [reverse] and [−] is common cross-linguistically (see Pope, 1976) • Given a certain feature combination, which features are to be realized? Features that are more marked have higher ‘realization needs’ (5)

a. b. c.

[−] is marked relative to [+] [reverse] is marked relative to [same] the absolute polarity of a [reverse,+] or [reverse,−] response is marked because it contrasts with the polarity of the antecedent

• Overview of main predictions (6)

a. b. c. d.

[same,+] can only be realized by yes [reverse,−] can only be realized by no [same,−] can be realized by yes or no [reverse,+] can be realized by yes or no

5

(7)

a.

In the case of [same,−] we expect a preference for no over yes because [−] is more marked than [same] (this is corroborated in Brasoveanu et al., 2011)

b.

In the case of [reverse,+] both features have high realization needs; across languages we see different strategies to satisfy these needs

• In English, [reverse,+] polarity phrases must be accompanied by a clause with ‘verum focus,’ reflecting the contrastive positive polarity of the response: (8)

A: Peter didn’t call. B: Yes, he DID. / No, he DID.

• Plausibly, the accompanying clause is obligatory because polarity particles themselves cannot carry the appropriate contrastive stress • The full paradigm: (9)

(10)

(11)

(12)

A: Peter called. / Did Peter call? B: Yes, he did. / *No, he did.

[same,+]

A: Peter called. / Did Peter call? B: *Yes, he didn’t. / No, he didn’t.

[reverse,−]

A: Peter didn’t call. / Did Peter not call? B: Yes, he didn’t. / No, he didn’t. (preference for no)

[same,−]

A: Peter didn’t call. / Did Peter not call? B: Yes, he DID. / No, he DID. (contrastive stress obligatory)

[reverse,+]

• Explanation of the division of labor between yes and no: – The fact that yes is used for [same] and [+], while no is used for [reverse] and [−], and the fact that this division of labor is common cross-linguistically, is not surprising given that [same] and [+] are the unmarked features, while [reverse] and [−] are the marked ones

4.3

Interim conclusions

• Main puzzle for the day has been solved: our account of polarity particles has been extended in such a way that it deals appropriately with negative questions and assertions • Crucial elements of the extended account: – A distinction between positive and negative possibilities

(semantic refinement)

– A distinction between absolute and relative polarity features

(syntactic refinement)

• In the remainder of the talk, we will consider additional support for the account, based on: – Disjunctive questions and assertions involving negation – Polarity particle systems in languages other than English 6

5

Disjunctive questions and assertions • Consider the following two alternative questions: (13)

Did Susan pass the exam, or did she fail? a. *Yes, she did. / *No, she did. b. *Yes, she didn’t. / *No, she didn’t.

(14)

Did Susan pass the exam, or didn’t she? a. Yes, she did. / *No, she did. b. *Yes, she didn’t. / No, she didn’t.

• Alternative questions are generally assumed not to license yes/no responses • Thus, the fact that (14) licenses yes/no responses is surprising • We have a straightforward account of this observation: – The question in (14) highlights one positive possibility and one negative possibility – This means that both [same,+] and [same,−] particle responses are licensed – This is exactly what we see in (14a) and (14b), respectively. • We also have an account for the fact that (13) does not license polarity particle responses: – The question in (14) highlights two positive possibilities – This means that [same,+] and [same,−] and [reverse,+] responses are not licensed – [reverse,−] is licensed, because there are positive antecedent possibilities – However, a [reverse,−] response rejects all the positive antecedent possibilities, which means in this case that it is contradictory (presupposing that Susan did do the exam) • Thus, disjunctive questions provide additional support for the distinction between positive and negative possibilities and the distinction between absolute and relative polarity features • This domain is explored in more detail in the paper

6

Typological considerations • Given the assumed distinction between absolute and relative polarity features, we expect to find languages with different polarity particle systems • In particular, we expect languages where particles don’t do double duty, unlike in English • We also expect to find different realization strategies in the case of [reverse,+] • In this section we will consider several languages with three polarity particles: – A language with two absolute particles and a specialized [reverse] particle (Romanian) – Several languages with a specialized particle for [reverse,+] ∗ based on an adversative [reverse] morpheme (German) ∗ or based on a special [+] morpheme (French, Swedish, Danish) 7

6.1

A dedicated [reverse] particle: the case of Romanian

• Particle inventory: da, nu, ba (Farkas, 2011) • Realization rules for Romanian: realization potential of polarity particles – da realizes [+] – nu realizes [−] – ba realizes [reverse] • Realization rules for Romanian: realization needs of polarity features – Absolute features must be realized, either by a particle or by an accompanying clause – [same] is never realized – [reverse] is always realized in [reverse,+] responses – [reverse] is optionally realized in [reverse,−] responses to assertions – [reverse] is never realized in [reverse,−] responses to questions • da realizes [+] (15)

(16)

[same,+] A: Paul a telefonat./A telefonat Paul? B: Da/*Nu, (a telefonat). [reverse,+] A: Paul nu a telefonat./Nu a telefonat Paul? B: Ba da/*Nu, (a telefonat).

‘Paul called./Did Paul call?’ ‘Yes / *No (he called)’. ‘P did not call./Did P not call?’ ‘Yes, he DID.’

• nu realizes [−] (17)

(18)

[same,−] A: Paul nu a telefonat./Nu a telefonat Paul? B: Nu, (nu a telefonat). [reverse,−] A: Paul a telefonat./A telefonat Paul? B: Nu, (nu a telefonat).

‘P did not call./Did P not call?’ ‘No, (he didn’t call).’ ‘Paul called./Did Paul call?’ ‘No, (he didn’t call).’

• ba realizes [reverse] (19)

(20)

[reverse,+] A: Paul nu a telefonat./Nu a telefonat Paul? B: Ba (da)/*nu, (a telefonat). [reverse,−] A: Paul a telefonat. B: (Ba) nu, (nu a telefonat).

‘P did not call./Did P not call?’ ‘Yes, he DID.’ ‘Paul called.’ ‘No, (he didn’t call).

8

• Absolute features must be realized (by particle or accompanying clause): (21)

a.

A: Paul nu a telefonat. B: *Ba. / Ba da. / Ba, a telefonat.

b.

A: Paul a telefonat. B: *Ba. / Ba nu, (nu a telefonat). / Ba, nu a telefonat.

‘Paul did not call.’ ‘Yes, he DID.’ ‘Paul called.’ ‘No, he DIDN’t.’

• Realization of [reverse] in different types of responses: – In [reverse,+] responses, [reverse] is always realized: see (19) – In [reverse,−] responses to assertions, [reverse] is optionally realized: (22)

[reverse,−] in reactions to assertions A: Paul a telefonat. B: (Ba) nu, (nu a telefonat).

‘Paul called.’ ‘No, he DIDN’T.’

– In [reverse,−] responses to questions, [reverse] is never realized: (23)

[reverse,−] in reactions to questions A: Nu a telefonat Paul? B: *Ba nu/Nu, (nu a telefonat).

‘Did Paul call?’ ‘No, he didn’t.’

• The Romanian polarity particle system and our markedness considerations – The existence of languages with a dedicated [reverse] particle and no dedicated [same] particle is in line with our markedness considerations – We predict that there are no languages exhibiting the opposite pattern—a dedicated [same] particle but no dedicated [reverse] particle – The behavior of the [reverse] particle is also in line with our markedness considerations: ∗ [reverse,+] is more marked than [reverse,−] and thus has higher realization needs ∗ Assertion reversal is more marked than question reversal: the former leads to a ‘conversational crisis’, while the latter doesn’t. • Main contrasts with English – Presence of a dedicated [reverse] particle – No overlap in the use of da and nu, because these polarity particles don’t do double duty – High realization needs of [reverse,+] are satisfied by obligatory [reverse] particle • Predictions concerning other three polarity particle systems with a dedicated [reverse] particle: – Realization of [+] could be optional, because [+] is relatively unmarked – In this case, solo [reverse] would be possible in [reverse,+] responses (Hungarian) – Realization of [reverse] could be obligatory throughout

9

6.2

A dedicated [reverse,+] particle: the case of French and German

• Languages with basic absolute polarity particles may have a special [reverse,+] because no absolute polarity particle can realize both features and yet both have high realization needs. • Special [reverse,+] particles may consist of a special [+] particle or a special [reverse] particle. 6.2.1

Languages with a special [+] particle for [reverse,+]: French

• Polarity particles in French: oui, non, si • Features realized by each particle: – oui realizes [+] (24)

[same,+] A: Claude est ` a la maison. B: Oui, (elle y est).

‘Claude is at home.’ ‘Yes, (she is.)’

– non realizes [−] (25)

[same,−] A: Claude n’est pas `a la maison. B: Non, (elle n’y est pas).

‘Claude is not at home.’ ‘No, (she isn’t).

– si realizes [reverse,+] (26)

(27)

6.2.2

[reverse,+] A: Claude n’est pas `a la maison. B: Si, (elle y est). [reverse,−] A: Claude est ` a la maison. B: *Si/Non, (elle n’y est pas).

‘Claude is not at home.’ ‘Yes, she IS.’ ‘Claude is at home.’ ‘No, (she isn’t).’

Languages with a special [reverse] particle for [reverse,+]: German

• Polarity particles in German: ja, nein, (ja) doch • Features realized by each particle: – ja realizes [+] (28)

[same,+] A: Katharina ist zu Hause? B: Ja, (sie ist zu Hause).

‘Katharina is at home.’ ‘Yes, she is.’

– nein realizes [−] (29)

[same,−] A: Katharina ist nicht zu Hause. B: Nein, (sie ist nicht zu Hause). 10

‘Katharina is not at home.” ‘No, she isn’t.’

– (ja) doch realizes [reverse,+] (30)

(31)

7

[reverse,+] A: Katharina ist nicht zu Hause. B: (Ja) doch, (sie ist zu Hause).

‘Katharina is not at home.’ ‘Yes, she IS.’

[reverse,−] A: Katharina ist zu Hause. B: *Doch/Nein, (sie ist nicht zu Hause).

‘Katharina is at home.’ ‘No, she isn’t.’

Conclusion • In order to account for the distribution and interpretation of polarity particles in responses to negative questions and assertions, we made two crucial distinctions: – A distinction between positive and negative possibilities

(semantic refinement)

– A distinction between absolute and relative polarity features

(syntactic refinement)

• Polarity particles realize polarity features • The particle inventory and realization rules may differ from language to language • However, we expect that the realization rules of any particular language are in line with the general principle that more marked features have higher realization needs • [reverse,+] is special in this respect, because both features have high realization needs, while it is unlikely that a language has a single particle that realizes both [reverse] and [+] • Across languages, we see different strategies to satisfy the high realization needs of [reverse,+]

References Brasoveanu, A., Farkas, D., and Roelofsen, F. (2011). Polarity particles and the anatomy of negative quantifiers. Manuscript, University of California Santa Cruz and ILLC, University of Amsterdam. Farkas, D. (2010). The grammar of polarity particles in Romanian. In Edges, Heads, and Projections: Interface properties, pages 87–124. John Benjamins Publishing Company. Farkas, D. (2011). Polarity particles in English and Romanian. Manuscript, UC Santa Cruz. Farkas, D. and Bruce, K. (2010). On reacting to assertions and polar questions. Journal of semantics, 27, 81–118. Pope, E. (1976). Questions and Answers in English. Mouton, The Hague.

11

Polarity particles in an inquisitive discourse model

Rather, we think of these polarity particles as realizing certain polarity features. • Polarity features are hosted by a syntactic node which we will refer to as PolP.

221KB Sizes 1 Downloads 201 Views

Recommend Documents

Polar initiatives in an inquisitive discourse model
Speaker bias for anchor is rooted in Addressee's authority over it. Prediction: • STQs should be good only in contexts where Sp is not a good source but the Ad is good source and where Sp has reason to believe Ad will commit to anchor. • (24) sho

Polarity particles and the anatomy of n-words
Sep 6, 2011 - (3). Nx(student/(x) ∧ step-forward/(x)). • If we had a way to detect .... Syntactically, PolP always attaches to a clausal node, which we call its ...

Polarity particles and the anatomy of n-words
Sep 6, 2011 - we need a more fine-grained formal representation of proposals. 3. • To see this, consider ... Still, they do not license the same polarity particles.

Polar initiatives and polarity particle responses in an ... -
Jan 30, 2012 - both the common theme and the primary variations found across ...... of sentences, i.e., the potential to set up discourse referents that may serve ...

Polar initiatives and polarity particle responses in an ... -
Jan 30, 2012 - both the common theme and the primary variations found across ..... that we started out with in section 2.1 we have to add one more ingredient.

An inquisitive dynamic epistemic logic
Dec 2, 2011 - is an equivalence relation on W. • V is a function that assigns a truth value to every atomic sentence in P, relative to every w ∈ W. The objects in ...

An Inquisitive Semantics with Witnesses
Examples quantifiers and inquisitiveness. • The existential quantifier inherits the inquisitive features of disjunction. • s |=g ∃x.P(x) iff there is some object d ∈ D such that d is in the denotation of P in all worlds w ∈ s. The state has

An inquisitive semantics with witnesses
Oct 31, 2011 - M = 〈DM ,IM 〉 a model such that DM = D and IM coincides with I as far as individual constants and function symbols are concerned, then M is called a model based on D, or simply a D-model. Definition 10 (States). A state is a set of

Aggregation Model of Marine Particles by Moments ...
Jul 11, 2008 - By classical probability theory, the k-th moment of the log-normal distribution. N(x) = 1. √. 2πxlnσ e−(lnx−lnµ)2. 2log2σ. (1) is defined as m(k) =.

Inquisitive semantics lecture notes
Jun 25, 2012 - reformulated as a recursive definition of the set |ϕ|g of models over a domain. D in which ϕ is true relative to an assignment g. The inductive ...

Attention! Might in Inquisitive Semantics
Nov 9, 2009 - Figure 1: Some examples of inquisitive sentences. Atoms. ... and |¬q|. So there are two functions from [ϕ] to [ψ] in this case, one mapping.

Attentive might in inquisitive semantics
Feb 16, 2010 - If John goes to London, will he fly British Airways? (5) a. Yes, if he ..... again form a new class of meaningful sentences, namely conjectures.

Inquisitive Logic
These reactions play a crucial role in the dynamics of conversation. Financial support from the ... new intuitive interpretation of the notion of support—a notion that will play a key role in the definition of inquisitive ...... and recalling that

Polarity and Modality
1.3 Chapter 4: Neg-raising and Positive Polarity: The View from Modals . 7. 1.4 Chapter 5: ..... tual Coercion. Paper presented at the West Coast Conference on Formal Linguistics 28; .... for licensing. I call 'domain of a PI π' a constituent .... p

Emission of spherical cesium-bearing particles from an early stage ...
Emission of spherical cesium-bearing particles from an early stage of the Fukushima nuclear accident.pdf. Emission of spherical cesium-bearing particles from ...

Generalized Inquisitive Logic
P to {0, 1}. We denote by ω the set of all indices. Definition 3 (States). A state is a set of indices. We denote by S the set of all states. Definition 4 (Support).

Radical inquisitive semantics
In much recent work, this notion is given a dynamic twist, and the meaning of a sentence is .... A translation of (1) into our formal language is: (4) p ∧ (q ∨ r).

Inquisitive Semantics - CiteSeerX
We introduce an inquisitive semantics for a language of propo- sitional logic .... For a declarative language, a standard way to define the interpretation of ..... What we have arrived at, is that there are, as we will call them, four possibilities f

Inquisitive Background.pdf
4 I firmly believe in the guiding precepts of my. organization. 5 My town or city is my home, and I will fight to defend. it. 6 I owe everything to another detective ...

Explorations in Discourse Topicality
is a “subjective character,” through whose perceptions material is presented. A subjective .... Figure 22: A text-internal deictic center and two types of access. Figure 23: .... 1 This material was first developed for the Advanced Language Analy

Radical inquisitive semantics
a parallel characterization of positive and negative responses. To illustrate this ... Definition 3 below recursively defines, for every sentence ϕ in our language,.

Might and Free Choice in Inquisitive Semantics
Apr 3, 2009 - semantics, the central notion of relatedness is compliance. It is predicted, ... ϕ is compliant with ψ if ϕ affirms or denies a possibility that ψ draws.

Polarity and Modality
Lastly I would like to thank for their love my grandmother, my sister and my mother ...... 'deny' (which denotes a DE function and licenses NPIs on its own, cf. ...... offers a landing site for the modal to raise to (it is labeled XP in the above LF)

Might and Free Choice in Inquisitive Semantics
Apr 3, 2009 - Support and drawing attention. Updating a stage I,Q,A with a for- mula ϕ consists in manipulating the states in I, Q and A. How a state s in I, Q or ...