On the Consistency of Deferred Acceptance when Priorities are Acceptant Substitutable Flip Klijn∗ March 2011 Abstract In the context of resource allocation on the basis of responsive priorities, Ergin (2002) identifies a necessary and sufficient condition for the deferred acceptance rule to satisfy a consistency principle. In this note we extend this result to the domain of substitutable priorities, complementing results of Kojima and Manea (2010) and Kumano (2009). JEL classification: D63, C78. Keywords: deferred acceptance, consistency

1

Introduction

In the context of resource allocation on the basis of responsive priorities, Ergin (2002) studies the deferred acceptance rule (Gale and Shapley, 1962). He establishes that Pareto efficiency, groupstrategyproofness, and consistency are equivalent properties. Moreover, he identifies a necessary and sufficient condition on the priority structure to guarantee that the deferred acceptance rule satisfies any of these properties. Kojima and Manea (2010) point out that in practice priorities may often be non-responsive but substitutable. For the more general framework with substitutable priorities, Kojima and Manea (2010) provide axiomatic characterizations of the deferred acceptance rule. In particular, they extend part of Ergin’s (2002) main result by showing that Pareto efficiency, groupstrategyproofness, and Maskin monotonicy are equivalent properties. Kumano (2009) complements these findings of Kojima and Manea (2010) by identifying a necessary and sufficient condition on the priority structure to guarantee that the deferred acceptance rule is Pareto efficient when priorities are substitutable. The combined results of Kumano (2009) and Kojima and Manea (2010) do not completely generalize Ergin’s (2002) main result since consistency of the deferred acceptance rule is not dealt with. In this note we fill this gap.

2

Model

The notation and description of the deferred acceptance rule is due to Kojima and Manea (2010). There is a set of agents N and a set of proper object types O. There is also a null object type, denoted ∅. Each object a ∈ O ∪ {∅} has quota qa ; q∅ = |N |. Each agent i is allocated exactly one object in O ∪ {∅}. An allocation is a vector µ = (µi )i∈N assigning object µi ∈ O ∪ {∅} to agent i. For each a ∈ O ∪ {∅}, we have that µa ≡ {i ∈ N : µi = a} satisfies |µa | ≤ qa . ∗

Institute for Economic Analysis (CSIC), Campus UAB, 08193 Bellaterra (Barcelona), Spain; e-mail: [email protected]. Financial support from Plan Nacional I+D+i (ECO2008–04784), the ConsoliderIngenio 2010 (CSD2006–00016) program, the Barcelona Graduate School of Economics and the Government of Catalonia (SGR2009–01142) is gratefully acknowledged.

1

The preferences of each agent i over the set of objects is represented by a linear order Ri . We denote by Pi the asymmetric part of Ri , i.e., aPi b if only if aRi b and a 6= b. An object a is acceptable to agent i if aPi ∅. Let R = (Ri )i∈N be the preference profile of all agents. For any N ′ ⊂ N , we write RN ′ = (Ri )i∈N ′ . We denote by A and R the sets of allocations and preference profiles, respectively. An allocation rule ϕ : R → A associates an allocation with each preference profile. At R, agent i is assigned object ϕi (R), and object a is assigned to the set of agents ϕa (R). An allocation µ Pareto dominates another allocation µ′ at R if µi Ri µ′i for all i ∈ N and µi Pi µ′i for some i ∈ N . An allocation is Pareto efficient at R if no allocation Pareto dominates it at R. An allocation rule ϕ is Pareto efficient if ϕ(R) is Pareto efficient at R for all R ∈ R. An allocation rule ϕ is group strategy-proof if there exist no N ′ ⊆ N and R, R′ ∈ R such that ′ ,R ′ ′ ′ ϕi (RN ′ N \N ′ )Ri ϕi (R) for all i ∈ N and ϕj (RN ′ , RN \N ′ )Pj ϕj (R) for some j ∈ N . A priority for a proper object a ∈ O is a correspondence Cha : 2N → 2N with Cha (N ′ ) ⊆ N ′ and |Cha (N ′ )| ≤ qa for all N ′ ⊆ N . We make the following two assumptions on each priority. First, Cha is substitutable, i.e., for all N ′ ⊂ N ′′ ⊆ N , Cha (N ′′ ) ∩ N ′ ⊆ Cha (N ′ ). Second, Cha is acceptant, i.e., for all N ′ ⊆ N , |Cha (N ′ )| = min(qa , |N ′ |). Let Ch ≡ (Cha )a∈O denote the (acceptant substitutable) priority structure. An allocation µ is individually rational at R if for all i ∈ N , µi Ri ∅. The allocation µ is blocked by a pair (i, a) ∈ N × O at (R, Ch) if aPi µi and i ∈ Cha (µa ∪ {i}). An allocation µ is stable at (R, Ch) if it is individually rational at R and is not blocked by any pair (i, a) ∈ N × O at (R, Ch). Since Ch is substitutable, the so-called deferred acceptance rule, denoted ϕCh , yields a stable allocation ϕCh (R) at (R, Ch) (Roth and Sotomayor, 1990, proof of Theorem 6.5). The allocation ϕCh (R) is obtained through the deferred acceptance algorithm as follows. ˜ 1 be Step 1: Each agent applies to his most preferred acceptable object under R (if any). Let N a 1 ˜ 1 ), the set of agents applying to object a. Object a tentatively accepts the agents in Na ≡ Cha (N a ˜ 1 \N 1 . and rejects the agents in N a a Step t, t ≥ 2: Each agent who was rejected at step t − 1 applies to his next preferred acceptable ˜ t be the new set of agents applying to object a. Object a object under R (if any). Let N a ˜ t ), and rejects the agents in (N t−1 ∪ tentatively accepts the agents in Nat ≡ Cha (Nat−1 ∪ N a a ˜ t) \ N t. N a a The algorithm terminates when each agent is either tentatively accepted by some object or has been rejected by every object that is acceptable to him. Each agent tentatively accepted by a proper object at the last step is assigned that object, and all other agents are assigned the null object. The allocation reached by the deferred acceptance rule is the agent-optimal stable allocation at (R, Ch). That is, ϕCh (R) is stable at (R, Ch), and all agents weakly prefer ϕCh (R) to any other stable allocation at (R, Ch) (Roth and Sotomayor, 1990, Theorem 6.8). Since efficiency is one of the goals of the social planner in resource allocation problems, Kojima and Manea (2010) develop necessary and sufficient conditions for the efficiency of the deferred acceptance rules. Proposition 1. (Kojima and Manea, 2010, Proposition 1) The following properties are equivalent. (i) ϕCh is Pareto efficient. (ii) ϕCh satisfies Maskin monotonicity.1 (iii) ϕCh is group strategy-proof. Kumano (2009) derives a generalization of the acyclicity condition introduced by Ergin (2002) 1

For the definition of Maskin monotonicity we refer to Kojima and Manea (2010) and Maskin (1999).

2

and shows that it is a sufficient and necessary condition on the priority structure to guarantee that ϕCh satisfies either of the properties in Proposition 1. A cycle is constituted of distinct i, j, k ∈ N and a, b ∈ O such that that there are disjoint (and possibly empty) sets Na , Nb ⊆ N \{i, j, k} satisfying (C) j 6∈ Cha (Na ∪ {i, j}), k 6∈ Cha (Na ∪ {j, k}), and i 6∈ Chb (Nb ∪ {k, i}). (S) |Na | = qa − 1 and |Nb | = qb − 1. If there is no cycle, then we say that the priority structure is acyclical. Proposition 2. (Kumano, 2009, Proposition 1) The following properties are equivalent. (i) ϕCh is Pareto efficient. (iv) Ch is acyclical. Combining Propositions 1 and 2 yields a partial generalization of the main result of Ergin (2002, Theorem 1), who considers acceptant responsive priority structures (which are a strict subclass of acceptant substitutable priority structures).2 The generalization of Ergin (2002, Theorem 1) is not complete since Kojima and Manea (2010) and Kumano (2009) do not consider the consistency of the (extended) deferred acceptance rule. In the next section we fill this gap.

3

Result

We first introduce consistency. Let Ch be a priority structure. An economy is a triple (N ′ , q ′ , RN ′ ) where N ′ ⊆ N and q ′ ≡ (qa′ )a∈O with qa′ ≤ qa for all a ∈ O. The extended deferred acceptance rule, denoted ϕ˜Ch , associates with each economy (N ′ , q ′ , RN ′ ) the allocation that is obtained by applying the (accordingly adapted) deferred acceptance algorithm to (N ′ , q ′ , RN ′ ) and the restricted priority structure (Cha |2N ′ ) . Given the original economy (N, q, R), an a∈O allocation µ for (N, q, R), and a subset of agents N ′ ⊂ N , the reduced economy of (N, q, R) with respect to µ and N ′ is the economy (N ′ , q µ , RN ′ ) where for all a ∈ O, qaµ ≡ qa − |µa \N ′ |. Consistency of the extended deferred acceptance rule requires that once an allocation for the original economy is determined and some agents receive their assigned objects before the others, the rule should not change the assigned objects of the remaining agents in the reduced economy. Formally, a priority structure Ch induces a consistent extended deferred acceptance rule ϕ˜Ch if for each N ′ ⊂ N and each preference profile R, µ|N ′ = ϕ˜Ch (N ′ , q µ , RN ′ ) where µ = ϕ˜Ch (N, q, R). The following result completes the generalization of Ergin’s (2002) main result. Proposition 3. Each property in Propositions 1 and 2 is equivalent to the consistency of the extended deferred acceptance rule ϕ˜Ch . Proof. In view of (i) ⇔ (iii) in Proposition 1, it is sufficient to prove that (i) ⇒ ϕ ˜Ch is consistent ⇒ (iii). The proof is an adaptation of Ergin’s (2002) proof. (i) ⇒ ϕ ˜Ch is consistent: Assume ϕ ˜Ch is not consistent. Then there are N ′ ⊂ N and R such that µ|N ′ 6= ϕ˜Ch (N ′ , q µ , RN ′ ) where µ = ϕ˜Ch (N, q, R). Since µ = ϕ˜Ch (N, q, R) = ϕ(R) is a stable allocation in the original economy (N, q, R), it immediately follows that µ|N ′ is stable in the reduced economy (N ′ , q µ , RN ′ ). Since priorities are substitutable it follows from Roth and Sotomayor (1990, Theorem 6.8) that ϕ˜Ch (N ′ , q µ , RN ′ ) Pareto dominates µ|N ′ in the reduced economy (N ′ , q µ , RN ′ ). Therefore, in the original economy, the allocation ν defined by  Ch ′ µ ϕ˜i (N , q , RN ′ ) if i ∈ N ′ ; νi ≡ µi if i ∈ N \N ′ 2

A priority structure Ch is responsive if for each a ∈ O, there is a linear order Ra on N such that for each N ⊆ N , Cha (N ′ ) equals the set of min(qa , |N ′ |) top ranked agents in N ′ under Ra . ′

3

Pareto dominates µ. Hence, ϕCh is not Pareto efficient. ϕ˜Ch is consistent ⇒ (iii): Assume ϕ ˜Ch is consistent. From the proof of Lemma 1 in P´ apai (2000) it follows that strategy-proofness and nonbossiness imply group strategyproofness.3 Since priorities are acceptant substitutable, it follows that for any object a ∈ O and any two sets of agents N ′ ⊂ N ′′ ⊆ N , |Cha (N ′ )| = min(qa , |N ′ |) ≤ min(qa , |N ′′ |) = |Cha (N ′′ )|. Therefore, the priorities satisfy the law of demand (Hatfield and Milgrom, 2005, page 923). Hence, by Theorems 11 and 12 in Hatfield and Milgrom (2005), ϕCh is strategy-proof. To complete the proof we show that ϕCh is nonbossy. Let i ∈ N and R, R′ ∈ R be such Ch ′ Ch Ch (R′ , R that ϕCh N \{i} ). Note that i (R) = ϕi (Ri , RN \{i} ). Let µ ≡ ϕ (R) and ν ≡ ϕ i µ since µi = νi , the reduced economies (N \{i}, q , RN \{i} ) and (N \{i}, q ν , RN \{i} ) are the same. Hence, ϕ ˜Ch (N \{i}, q µ , RN \{i} ) = ϕ˜Ch (N \{i}, q ν , RN \{i} ). On the other hand, by consistency, µ|N \{i} = ϕ˜Ch (N \{i}, q µ , RN \{i} ) and ν|N \{i} = ϕ˜Ch (N \{i}, q ν , RN \{i} ). Hence, µ|N \{i} = ν|N \{i} , which together with µi = νi implies that ϕCh (R) = µ = ν = ϕCh (Ri′ , RN \{i} ). Hence, ϕCh is nonbossy.

References ˙ (2002): “Efficient Resource Allocation on the Basis of Priorities,” EconometErgin, H. I. rica, 70(6), 2489–2497. Gale, D., and L.S. Shapley (1962): “College Admissions and the Stability of Marriage,” The American Mathematical Monthly, 69(1), 9–15. Hatfield, J.W., and P. Milgrom (2005): “Matching with Contracts,” American Economic Review, 95(4), 913-935. Kojima, F., and M. Manea (2010): rica, 78(2), 633-653.

“Axioms for Deferred Acceptance,” Economet-

Kumano, T. (2009): “Efficient Resource Allocation under Acceptant Substitutable Priorities,” Working paper, Washington University in St. Louis. Maskin, E. (1999): “Nash Equilibrium and Welfare Optimality,” Review of Economic Studies, 66(1), 23–38. P´ apai, S. (2000): “Strategyproof Assignment by Hierarchical Exchange,” Econometrica, 68(6), 1403–1433. Roth, A.E., and M.A.O. Sotomayor (1990): Two-Sided Matching: A Study in Game-Theoretic Modeling and Analysis. Econometric Society Monograph Series. New York: Cambridge University Press.

3 An allocation rule ϕ is strategy-proof if there exist no i ∈ N and R, R′ ∈ R such that ϕi (Ri′ , RN\{i} )Pi ϕi (R). An allocation rule ϕ is nonbossy if for all i ∈ N and all R, R′ ∈ R, ϕi (R) = ϕi (Ri′ , RN\{i} ) implies ϕ(Ri′ , RN\{i} ) = ϕ(R).

4

On the Consistency of Deferred Acceptance when Priorities are ... - Csic

Roth, A.E., and M.A.O. Sotomayor (1990): Two-Sided Matching: A Study in Game-Theoretic. Modeling and Analysis. Econometric Society Monograph Series.

84KB Sizes 0 Downloads 229 Views

Recommend Documents

On the Consistency of Deferred Acceptance when ... - Semantic Scholar
An allocation µ Pareto dominates another allocation µ′ at R if µiRiµ′ ... at (R,Ch). Since Ch is substitutable, the so-called deferred acceptance rule, denoted ...

On the Consistency of Deferred Acceptance when ... - Semantic Scholar
Working paper, Washington University in St. Louis. Maskin, E. (1999): “Nash Equilibrium and Welfare Optimality,” Review of Economic Stud- ies, 66(1), 23–38.

On the Consistency of Deferred Acceptance when ...
There is a set of agents N and a set of proper object types O. There is also a null object ... An allocation is a vector µ = (µi)i∈N assigning object µi ∈ O ∪ {∅} to.

AXIOMS FOR DEFERRED ACCEPTANCE Department of ... - CiteSeerX
Apr 14, 2009 - Korkmaz, ˙I., H. Gökçen, and T. C¸etinyokus (2008): “An analytic hierarchy ... (1983b): “Problems of fair division and the Egalitarian solution,” ...

Axioms for Deferred Acceptance - CiteSeerX
the Office of the Econometric Society (contact information may be found at the website ... achievements in mathematics and science go to the best engineering univer- sities. Stability is regarded as a .... tion rules over the domain of pairs of respo

Axioms for Deferred Acceptance - CiteSeerX
achievements in mathematics and science go to the best engineering univer- ...... Two-Sided Matching Based Decision Support System for Military Personnel ...

Axioms for Deferred Acceptance - CiteSeerX
For example, schools in Boston give higher priority to students who live nearby or .... Kesten (2006) showed that the deferred acceptance rule and the top trading cycle rule for ..... light on the mechanics of the deferred acceptance algorithm.

AXIOMS FOR DEFERRED ACCEPTANCE Department of ... - CiteSeerX
Apr 14, 2009 - and science go to the best engineering universities–and stability can be ...... sided matching based decision support system for military ...

Equilibria under Deferred Acceptance: Dropping ...
Jun 2, 2016 - s3 s4 s5 s6 h1 h2 h3 h2 h∗. 1 h1 h3 h∗. 2 h2 s∗. 1 s∗. 4 s5 h∗. 1 h∗. 3 h∗. 2 h3 h∗. 3 s∗. 2 s∗. 5 s∗. 6 s3 s6 s∗. 3 s1 s4. Table 1: Preferences ...

Equilibria under Deferred Acceptance: Dropping Strategies, Filled ...
Oct 2, 2013 - monio Autónomo Fondo Nacional de Financiamiento para la Ciencia, la Tecnología y la ...... College Admissions and the Stability of Marriage.

On the Convexity of Precedence Sequencing Games - Csic
theory and cooperative game theory. Hamers et al. (1996) and Van Velzen and Hamers (2002) investigate the class of sequencing situations as in considered ...

When Higher Bars Are Not Larger Quantities: On ...
Apr 19, 2012 - 3Department of Cognitive and Learning Sciences, Michigan Technological .... Graph literacy is a skill typically acquired through formal education, ..... data, which corresponds to an advanced level of graph comprehension (for.

The Role of Forensics When Departments and Programs are Targeted ...
Recent economic conditions in the United States are taking their toll on the educational institutions in this country. One dilemma resulting from this predicament is the potentiality a department of communication and/or a forensic program may be targ

The suboptimality of commitment equilibrium when agents are learning
Nov 15, 2011 - data. We show that the optimal monetary policy drives the economy far from the ... the long run however, as agents start learning about the true central ...... then, we argue that these arbitrary constraints can be made so big that ...

The Role of Random Priorities
Apr 8, 2017 - †Université Paris 1 and Paris School of Economics, 106-112 Boulevard de l'Hopital, ... The designer selects a random priority rule, and agents.

Acceptance of health services on mobile phones: A ...
OBJECTIVE: This study examined health consumers' perceptions of mobile ...... For promoting healthy lifestyles, there is an Internet service to schedule exercise ...

ON THE CONSISTENCY OF THE 1 1-CA FRAGMENT ...
modification: we start with a recursively saturated elementary extension of. Parsons' .... many free variables x, ¯y and every finite tuple ¯n of elements of M, there is ... abiding to schema V, whose domain is the set of all natural numbers, and.

ON THE CONSISTENCY OF THE 1 1-CA FRAGMENT ...
model-theoretic consistency proof produces a model of T whose 1. 1-sets consist only of ..... Now, the set {〈a, n, m〉 ∈ N : (N,I) N Dw,x,y,u[p, a, n, m]} is a predica-.

Consistency of individual differences in behaviour of the lion-headed ...
1999 Elsevier Science B.V. All rights reserved. Keywords: Aggression .... the data analysis: Spearman rank correlation co- efficient with exact P values based on ...

When Irish Eyes Are Smiling
NVHDP Tune: March 2013. When Irish Eyes Are Smiling. Ernest Ball. Published 1912. D major. Form as written.... D.. A.. D... D7.... G..... D.... 9.. G.. D.. B7.. E... A7.... 17.. D.. A.. D... D7.... G..... D..

Estimating the Structural Credit Risk Model When Equity Prices Are ...
Abstract. The transformed-data maximum likelihood estimation (MLE) method for struc- tural credit risk models developed by Duan (1994) is extended to account for the fact that observed equity prices may have been contaminated by trading noises. With

Be Fearful When Households Are Greedy: The ... - David C. Yang
the value-weighted market index from the Center for Research in Security Prices (CRSP). We use the ..... cloud the interpretation of our findings. ..... Gruber, Martin J, 1996, Another puzzle: The growth in actively managed mutual funds, The.