March 23, 2006 10:51 WSPC/151-IGTR

00081

International Game Theory Review, Vol. 8, No. 1 (2006) 111–126 c World Scientific Publishing Company 

COALITION FORMATION IN GAMES WITHOUT SYNERGIES

SERGIO CURRARINI Dipartimento di Scienze Economiche Universit` a Ca’ Foscari di Venezia, Italy and School for Advanced Studied in Venice (SSAV), Venezia, Italy MARCO A. MARINI∗ Istituto di Scienze Economiche Universit` a degli Studi di Urbino “Carlo Bo”, Italy and London School of Economics, UK [email protected]

This paper establishes sufficient conditions for the existence of a stable coalition structure in the “coalition unanimity” game of coalition formation, first defined by Hart and Kurz (1983) and more recently studied by Yi (1997, 2003). Our conditions are defined on the strategic form game used to derive the payoffs of the game of coalition formation. We show that if no synergies are generated by the formation of coalitions, a stable coalition structure always exists provided that players are symmetric and either the game exhibits strategic complementarity or, if strategies are substitutes, the best reply functions are contractions. Keywords: Coalition formation; synergies; strong Nash equilibrium; symmetric games. JEL Classification Number: C7

1. Introduction This paper is a contribution to the study of stable coalition structures in games of coalition formation. We follow the stream of literature on coalition formation that views cooperation as a two stage process: a first stage in which players form coalitions, and a second stage in which formed coalitions interact in some underlying “economic” strategic setting (see Bloch (1997) and Yi (2003) for extensive surveys of this approach). This process is formally described by a strategic form game of coalition formation, in which a given “rule” maps players’ announcements of coalitions into a well defined coalition structure, which in turns determines the equilibrium strategies at the second stage when the “economic” game is played by ∗ Corresponding

author. Istituto di Scienze Economiche, Universit` a degli Studi di Urbino “Carlo Bo”, Via Saffi, 42, 60129, Urbino, Italy. 111

March 23, 2006 10:51 WSPC/151-IGTR

112

00081

S. Currarini & M. A. Marini

coalitions. In this paper we focus on the “gamma” or “coalitional unanimity” rule, first considered in Hart and Kurz (1983) and also studied in Yi (2003) for partition function games, predicting that a coalition forms if and only if all of its members have announced it. Our analysis is based on a primitive description of strategic possibilities of players and coalitions in the “economic” game by means of a strategic form game G. This game exhaustively describes the actions available to players, both as individuals and as coalitions, and the way in which any profile of actions induces a payoff allocation for players. More specifically, in any given partition, coalitional strategy sets are given by the Cartesian products of their members’ strategy sets, and coalitional payoff functions are given by the sum of their members’ payoff functions, as these are described by G. In this context, the formation of a coalition does not expand coalitional members strategic possibilities with respect to G, if not by allowing them to choose their strategies in a coordinated manner. In other words, each game G(π) associated with a second stage in which the partition π has formed, contains no additional information to G other than the configuration of coalitions. This framework rules out the possibility of coalitional synergies, by this meaning any advantage in forming a coalition that is not related to the coordination of members’ strategies (as, for example in R&D cooperation games). The focus on the properties of the strategic form game G is the main difference between our approach and that of, for example, Yi (1977, 2003), in which conditions for the existence of stable coalition structures are derived in terms of the properties of the equilibrium payoffs of the game G(π) as a function of the partition π. Indeed, although Yi (1997, 2003) refers to a symmetry assumption directly defined on a strategic form game to be played at the second stage of the coalition formation process, this assumption is solely used to obtain a simpler description of equilibrium payoffs, that end up depending only on the number of players in each coalition. If interpreted as a feature of all possible games to be played at the second stage (that is, for all possible partitions), this symmetry condition rules out the presence of synergies, and is hardly compatible with the kind of situations covered by Yi’s analysis. To rule out such ambiguities, we therefore reformulate the symmetry assumption as a feature of the primitive game G, and explicitly derive all games G(π) under the assumption of no synergies. While it is well known that the existence of synergies can lead to instability even in games which are ex-ante symmetric (that is, symmetric within coalitions and not across coalitions, see Yi (2003) and Sec. 4 of the present paper), what conditions would, in the absence of synergies, ensure the existence of a stable coalition structure is still an open question. We show that our symmetry assumption on G (which, together with the absence of synergies implies ex-post symmetry in each game G(π)), is sufficient for the existence of a stable coalition structure, provided that the effect of externalities satisfies two properties. First, the cross-effect of player’s actions on other players’ payoffs must be monotone, both across players and across strategy profiles (we will refer to the classes of positive and negative externalities). Second, payoff functions must either exhibit strategic complementarity (in the sense

March 23, 2006 10:51 WSPC/151-IGTR

00081

Coalition Formation in Games without Synergies

113

of Bulow et al. (1985)) or generate best replies which are contractions (in other words, strategic substitutability should not be too strong). Typical examples of games belonging to these classes are cartel formation in Cournot and Bertrand oligopolies, public good games, environmental games. We can interpret our results directly in terms of the effect on the profitability of joint deviations in the coalition unanimity game. Consider the strategy profile inducing the grand coalition, and any joint deviation by coalition S ⊂ N . Under positive externalities, S will tend to lower the level of its members’ strategies with respect to the efficient level. Strategic complementarity implies, however, that players in N \S, now organized as singletons, will themselves lower their strategies, thereby hurting S through the effect of positive externalities. Hence, S’s deviation are in general not profitable. Strategic substitutes have the opposite properties: if S drops out from N wishing to produce less under positive externalities (and more under negative), then the players in N \S react by producing more under positive (and less under negative), thereby benefiting coalition S. If this reaction is large enough to compensate the decrease on the payoff of the members of S caused, through the cross effect, by the decrease in their strategies, S’s deviation is profitable. The assumption that best replies are contractions limits the magnitude of such reactions and, together with the symmetry and the no synergies assumptions, ensures the stability of the grand coalition. It should however be noted that the techniques used in this paper strongly rely on the symmetry of the model. For this reason, although our results remain true in presence of small asymmetries, the present analysis does not directly extends to general games. The paper is organized as follows. Section 2 describes the setup, defines the game of coalition formation and discusses our main assumptions. In Sec. 3 the main results are presented and the role of synergies is explained through a simple economic example.

2. The Setup 2.1. The strategic form game G Players’ interaction is described by the game in strategic form G = (N, (Xi , ui )i∈N ) in which N is a finite set of n players, Xi is the set of strategies of player i and n ui : XN → R+ is the payoff function of player i, for all i ∈ N , where XN = i=1 Xi . We make two main assumptions on G. Assumption 2.1. (Symmetric Players). Xi = X ⊂ R for all i ∈ N . Moreover, for all x ∈ XN and all permutationsa p : N → N : up(i) (xp(1) , . . . , xp(n) ) = ui (x1 , . . . , xn ). aA

(2.1)

definition of symmetry based on “pairwise” permutations, contained in previous versions of the paper, is equivalent to the present definition which applies to general permutations. We thank an anonymous referee for pointing this out.

March 23, 2006 10:51 WSPC/151-IGTR

114

00081

S. Currarini & M. A. Marini

Assumption 2.2. (Monotone Externalities). One of the following two cases must hold: 1. Positive externalities: ui (x) strictly increasing in xN \i for all i and all x ∈ XN ; 2. Negative externalities: ui (x) strictly decreasing in xN \i for all i and all x ∈ XN . Assumption 2.1 requires that all players have the same strategy set, and that players payoff functions are symmetric, by this meaning that any permutation of strategies across players induces an analogous permutation in payoffs. Assumption 2.2 requires that the cross effect on payoffs of a change of strategy have the same sign for all players and for all strategy profiles. 2.2. Coalition formation in G A coalition in the game G is defined as a subset of players S ⊂ N , while the set N itself is denoted as the “grand coalition”. A configuration of coalitions is described by the notion of a coalition structure, that is, a partition of the set N .b One way of studying how coalitions emerge in the system is to consider a game of coalition formation in which each player i ∈ N announces a coalition S  i to which he would like to belong; for each profile σ = (S1 , S2 , . . . , Sn ) of announcements, a partition π(σ) of N is assumed to be induced on the system. This approach was first considered by Von Neumann and Morgenstern (1944), and more recently studied by Hart and Kurz (1983) and by part of the literature on coalition formation. The rule according to which π(σ) originates from σ is obviously a crucial issue for the prediction of which coalitions will emerge in equilibrium. Here we concentrate on the “gamma” rule, predicting that a coalition emerges if and only if all its members have declared it (from which the name of “unanimity rule” also used to describe this game, see Yi (2003)). Formally: π(σ) = {Si (σ) : i ∈ N } where

 Si Si (σ) = {i}

if Si = Sj for all j ∈ Si otherwise

(2.2)

(2.3)

The gamma rule is used to derive a payoff function vi mapping from the set of all players’ announcements Σ into the set of real numbers. The payoff functions vi are obtained by associating with each partition π = {S1 , S2 , . . . , Sm } a game in strategic form G(π) = ({1, 2, . . . , m}, (XS1 , XS2 , . . . , XSm ), (US1 , US2 , . . . , USm )),

(2.4)

in which XSk is the strategy set of coalition Sk and USk : Πm k=1 XSk → R+ is the payoff function of coalition Sk , for all k = 1, 2, . . . , m. The game G(π) describes the b We

remind here that a partition of N is a collection {B1 , B2 , . . . , Bm } of subsets of N with empty pairwise intersections and whose union coincides with N .

March 23, 2006 10:51 WSPC/151-IGTR

00081

Coalition Formation in Games without Synergies

115

interaction of coalitions after π has formed as a result of players announcements in Γ. The unique Nash equilibrium of the game G(π) gives the payoff of each coalition in π; within coalitions, a fix distribution rule yields the payoffs of individual members. (see Bloch (1997) and Yi (2003) for surveys). In this paper, we use the game G to derive all games G(π), one for each parti  tion π, by simply assuming that XSk = i∈Sk Xi and USk = i∈Sk ui , for every coalition Sk ∈ π. Note that each G(π) preserves the original features of the game G, without endowing coalitions with any additional strategic possibility. Forming a coalition does not enlarge the set of strategies available to its members and does not modify the way payoffs within a coalition originate from the strategies chosen by players in N . Thus, here the only advantage for players to form coalitions is to coordinate their strategies in the game G in order to obtain a coalitional efficient outcome. This approach is appropriate for many well known games such as Cournot and Bertrand cartel formation and public good games, but rules out an important driving force of coalition formation, i.e., the exploitation of synergies, typically arising for instance in R&D alliances or mergers among firms yielding some sort of economies of scales. We point out that the assumption that G(π) admits a unique Nash equilibrium for all π, commonly used in the literature to obtain a well defined payoff functions for the game Γ, does not appear to be very restrictive in the class of games covered by this paper (see Sec. 3). In particular, the contraction condition we use in Proposition 3.2 directly ensures the uniqueness of the Nash equilibrium of G(π). Moreover, the property of increasing differences used in Proposition 3.1 together with Assumptions 2.1 and 2.2 implies that either the greatest or the least element of the set of Nash equilibria Pareto dominates all other elements of this set (which of the two depends on the sign of the externality), and represents therefore a natural selection. We finally define a stable coalition structure for the game Γ as a partition induced by a Strong Nash Equilibrium strategy profile. Definition 2.1. The partition π is a stable coalition structure for the game Γ if π = π(σ ∗ ) for some σ ∗ with the following property: there exists no S ⊆ N and σS ∈ ΣS such that ∗ ∗ vi (σS , σN \S ) ≥ vi (σ ),

for all i ∈ S

(2.5)

for some h ∈ S.

(2.6)

and ∗ ∗ vh (σS , σN \S ) > vh (σ ),

The game Γ is therefore defined by the triplet (N, Σ, (vi )i∈N ), with player i ∈ N receiving payoff vi (σ) ≡ ui (x(π(σ)) if profile σ is played. In this paper we will focus on games in which the strategy profiles at which coalitions maximize their aggregate payoff require all members to play the same

March 23, 2006 10:51 WSPC/151-IGTR

116

00081

S. Currarini & M. A. Marini

strategy. Formally, we will make the following assumption:  Assumption 2.3. For all S ⊆ N , if x∗S ∈ arg maxxS ∈XS i∈S ui (xS , xN \S ), then x∗i = x∗j , for all i, j ∈ S, and for all xN \S ∈ XN \S . Since we are not explicitly allowing for side payments, this assumption directly S induces the equal split imputation us = U |S| within each coalition at equilibrium. This restriction of efficient strategies is not, of course, without loss of generality. We show in the next lemmata that this property is implied either by appropriate concavity conditions on payoff functions or by strategic complementarities. In particular, strict quasiconcavity of payoff functions implies the desired property under our symmetry Assumption 2.1. Failing quasiconcavity, strict concavity of each player’s payoff function in her own strategy is sufficient when the game is additive, in the sense that each player’s payoff depends on his own strategy and on the sum of all players’ strategies. Finally, all concavity assumptions can be dispensed of if the payoff functions exhibit increasing differences. Lemma 2.1. Let X be convex and ui (x) be strictly quasiconcave for all i ∈ N . Then, Assumption 2.3 holds. Proof. See appendix. Lemma 2.2. Let X be convex, ui (x) be strictly concave in xi and ui (x) =  ui (xi , j∈N xj ) for all i ∈ N . Then, Assumption 2.3 holds. Proof. See appendix. Lemma 2.3. Let ui (x) satisfy increasing differences in XN for all i ∈ N (see Definition 3.1 in Sec. 3). Then, Assumption 2.3 holds. Proof. See the proof of Lemma 6 in Currarini and Marini (2004). 3. Results In this section we obtain two main results: in Theorem 3.1 we show that under our symmetry Assumptions 2.1–2.3, all games G with strategic complements admit the grand coalition as a stable coalition structure for the associated game Γ. In Theorem 3.2 we then show that the same result extends to games with strategic substitutes under a contraction assumption, which bounds the effect of strategic substitutability on the (negative) slope of reaction maps. Instead of directly showing that the unique strategy profile σ ∗ yielding the grand coalition in the game Γ is not improved upon by any coalitional joint deviation, we proceed by proving that a property of the game G, shown by Yi (2003) to imply the stability of the grand coalition in the associated game Γ, is satisfied under our assumptions. This property is indicated by Yi (2003) as one of the main features

March 23, 2006 10:51 WSPC/151-IGTR

00081

Coalition Formation in Games without Synergies

117

of coalitional games with positive spillovers, although being formally independent. It requires that at the equilibrium profile of strategies associated with any given partition of the set of players, the members of smaller coalitions are better off than the members of larger coalitions. In terms of the present notation, it is stated as follows: Condition 3.1. Let π be a partition of N , and let S ∈ π and T ∈ π. If |T | ≥ |S| then us (x(π)) ≥ ut (x(π)). We proceed by first establishing a basic preparatory lemma, showing that in the present setting Condition 3.1 can be reformulated in terms of the magnitude of the strategies played within T and S at x(π). This result will allow us to work directly on these magnitude in the following lemmata and propositions. Some additional notation is required. Notation 3.1. We will be considering an arbitrary partition π of N , containing the sets S ⊂ N and T ⊂ N , with |T | ≥ |S|. We will denote by xs ∈ X and by xt ∈ X the strategies chosen by each member of S and T at the equilibrium profile x(π), respectively.c It will be useful to refer to a partition of the coalition T into the disjoint subsets T1 and T2 of T , such that |T1 | = |S|. To keep notation simple, we will refer to players’ payoffs omitting from the argument all the strategies played by players in N \(T ∪ S), implicitly setting such strategies at their equilibrium level in x(π). More precisely, we will use the following notational convention: for any triplet of strategies x, y and z, we let: ((x, y), z) ≡ ((x)i∈T1 , (y)i∈T2 , (z)i∈S , (xj (π))j∈N \(T ∪S) ),

(3.1)

where (x)i∈T1 denotes the joint strategy xT1 ∈ XT1 in which xi = x for all i ∈ T1 , and the same notational convention applies to (y)i∈T2 and (z)i∈S . It follows that the triplet ((xt , xt ), xs ) identifies the equilibrium profile x(π). With these notational conventions in mind, we can establish the first lemma. Lemma 3.1. Let Assumptions 2.1–2.3 hold. Let S ⊂ N and T ⊂ N be such that |T | ≥ |S|. Then: (i) Under Positive Externalities, xs ≤ xt implies us (x(π)) ≥ ut (x(π)); (ii) Under Negative Externalities, xs ≥ xt implies us (x(π)) ≥ ut (x(π)). Proof. We first prove the result for the case of positive externalities. Consider coalitions T1 , T2 and S such that |T1 | = |S| and such that {T1 , T2 } is a partition of T . By definition of x(π), the utility of each member of S is maximized by the c We

remind here that by Assumption 2.3, at x(π) all members of the same coalition play the same strategy.

March 23, 2006 10:51 WSPC/151-IGTR

118

00081

S. Currarini & M. A. Marini

strategy profile xS , in which each member of S plays xs . Using the definition of us and of xs we write: us ((xt , xt ), xs ) ≥ us ((xt , xt ), xt ).

(3.2)

By Assumption 2.2.1, if xs ≤ xt then us ((xt , xt ), xt ) ≥ us ((xs , xt ), xt ).

(3.3)

Finally, by Assumption 2.1 and the fact that |T1 | = |S|, we obtain us ((xs , xt ), xt ) = ut1 ((xt , xt ), xs ) = ut ((xt , xt ), xs ),

(3.4)

implying, together with (3.2) and (3.3), that us (x(π)) = us ((xt , xt ), xs ) ≥ ut ((xt , xt ), xs ) = ut (x(π)).

(3.5)

The case of negative externalities (Assumption 2.2.2) is proved along similar lines. Consider again coalitions T1 , T2 and S. Inequality (3.2) holds independently of the sign of the externality. By negative externalities, if xs ≥ xt then us ((xt , xt ), xt ) ≥ us ((xs , xt ), xt ).

(3.6)

As before, we use Assumption 2.1 and the fact that |T1 | = |S| to obtain us ((xs , xt ), xt ) = ut ((xt , xt ), xs ),

(3.7)

us (x(π)) = us (xt , xs ) ≥ ut (xt , xs ) = ut (x(π)).

(3.8)

and, therefore, that

Remark 3.1. It can be easily shown that the statements in Lemma 3.1 hold with the “if and only if” operator. We omit the proof of this fact since it is not necessary for our results. We are now ready to establish our first result: symmetric games with increasing differences satisfy Condition 3.1. Increasing differences are defined as follows: Definition 3.1. The payoff function ui exhibits increasing differences on XS × XN \S with respect to the partial order > if for all S, xS ∈ XS , xS ∈ XS , xN \S ∈ XN \S and xN \S ∈ XN \S such that xS > xS and xN \S > xN \S we have ui (xS , xN \S ) − ui (xS , xN \S ) > ui (xS , xN \S ) − ui (xS , xN \S ),

(3.9)

where xS > xS means that all elements of xS are weakly greater than the corresponding elements of xS , with strict inequality for at least one element, and the same convention is applied to xN \S > xN \S . If ui exhibits increasing differences on XS × XN \S for all S ⊂ N , we say that it has increasing differences on XN . Proposition 3.1. Let Assumptions 2.1 and 2.2 hold, and let π, T and S be defined as in Notation 3.1. Let ui have increasing differences on XN , for all i ∈ N . Then: (i) Positive Externalities imply xs ≤ xt ; (ii) Negative Externalities imply xs ≥ xt .

March 23, 2006 10:51 WSPC/151-IGTR

00081

Coalition Formation in Games without Synergies

119

Proof. (i) Suppose that, contrary to our statement, positive externalities hold and xs > xt . By increasing differences of ui for all i ∈ N (and using the fact that the sum of functions with increasing difference has itself increasing differences), we obtain: us ((xs , xt ), xs ) − us ((xs , xt ), xt ) ≥ us ((xt , xt ), xs ) − us ((xt , xt ), xt ).

(3.10)

By definition of xs we also have: us ((xt , xt ), xs ) − us ((xt , xt ), xt ) ≥ 0.

(3.11)

Conditions (3.10) and (3.11) directly imply: us ((xs , xt ), xs ) − us ((xs , xt ), xt ) ≥ 0.

(3.12)

Referring again to the partition of T into the disjoint coalitions T1 and T2 as defined in Notation 3.1, an application of the symmetry Assumption 2.1 yields: us ((xs , xt ), xs ) = ut1 ((xs , xt ), xs ); us ((xs , xt ), xt ) = ut1 ((xt , xt ), xs ).

(3.13)

Conditions (3.12) and (3.13) imply: ut1 ((xs , xt ), xs ) ≥ ut1 ((xt , xt ), xs ).

(3.14)

Positive externalities and the assumption that xs > xt imply: ut2 ((xs , xt ), xs ) > ut2 ((xt , xt ), xs ).

(3.15)

Summing up Conditions (3.14) and (3.15), and using the definition of T1 and T2 , we obtain: ut ((xs , xt ), xs ) > ut ((xt , xt ), xs ),

(3.16)

which contradicts the assumption that xt maximizes the utility of T given xs . The case (ii) of negative externalities is proved along similar lines. Suppose that xs < xt . Conditions (3.12) and (3.13), which are independent of the sign of the externalities, hold, so that (3.14) follows. Negative externalities also imply that if xs < xt then (3.15) follows. We therefore again obtain Condition (3.16) and a contradiction. Proposition 3.1 and a direct application of Lemma 3.1 and Proposition 4.7 in Yi (2003) yields the following theorem, establishing the stability of the grand coalition. Theorem 3.1. Let Assumptions 2.1 and 2.2 hold, and let ui exhibits increasing differences on XN , for all i ∈ N . Then Condition 3.1 holds. This implies that the grand coalition N is a stable coalition structure in the game of coalition formation Γ derived from the game in strategic form G. Proof. By Proposition 3.1, positive externalities imply that for all π, at x(π) larger coalitions choose larger strategies than smaller coalitions, while the opposite holds

March 23, 2006 10:51 WSPC/151-IGTR

120

00081

S. Currarini & M. A. Marini

under negative externalities. By Lemma 3.1, this implies Condition 3.11. The result of Proposition 4.7 in Yi (2003) shows that Condition 1 directly implies the stability of the grand coalition in Γ. To provide a sketch of that proof, we note that any coalitional deviation from the strategy profile σ ∗ yielding the grand coalition induces a coalition structure in which all members outside the deviating coalitions appear as singleton. Since these players are weakly better off than any of the deviating members (by Condition 1), and since all players were receiving the same payoff at σ ∗ , a strict improvement of the deviating coalition would contradict the efficiency of the outcome induced by the grand coalition. The stability of the efficient coalition structure π ∗ = {N } in this class of games can be intuitively explained as follows. In games with increasing differences, players strategies are strategic complements, and best replies are therefore positively sloped. Also, positive externalities imply that the deviation of a coalition S ⊂ N is typically associated with a lower level of S’s members’ strategies with respect to the efficient profile x(π ∗ ), and with a higher level in games with negative externalities (see Lemma 3.2 below). If strategies are the quantity of produced public good (positive externalities), S will try to free ride on non members by reducing its production; if strategies are emissions of pollutant (negative externalities), S will try to emit more and take advantage of non members’ lower emissions. The extent to which these deviations will be profitable ultimately depend on the reaction of non members. In the case of positive externalities, S will benefit from an increase of non members’ production levels; however, strategic complementarity implies that the decrease of S’s production levels will be followed by a decrease of the produced levels of non members. Similarly, the increase of S’s pollutant emissions will induce higher pollution levels by non members. Free riding is therefore little profitable in these games. From the above discussion, it is clear that deviations can be profitable only if best reply functions are negatively sloped, that is, strategies must be substitutes in G. However, the above discussion suggests that some “degree” of substitutability may still be compatible with stability. Indeed, if S’s decrease in the production of public good is followed by a moderate increase in the produced level of non members, S may still not find it profitable to deviate from the efficient profile induced by π ∗ . We will show that if the absolute value of the slope of the reaction maps is bounded above by 1, the stability result of Theorem 3.1 extends to games with strategic substitutes. Notation 3.2. For each coalition S ⊂ N , we define by fS (xN \S ) the reaction map of S as a function of the vector of strategies played by players who are not in S: fS (xN \S ) ≡ arg max

xS ∈XS

 i∈S

ui (xS , xN \S ).

(3.17)

March 23, 2006 10:51 WSPC/151-IGTR

00081

Coalition Formation in Games without Synergies

121

Note that under Assumption 2.3 for all xN \S the vector fS (xN \S ) can be written in the form fS (xN \S ) = fs (xN \S ) · e

(3.18)

where e denoted the s-dimensional unitary vector and fs (xN \S ) ∈ X. The reaction of S can therefore be represented in terms of the scalar fs (xN \S ). The next lemma characterizes the reaction map of T1 . We make use of the notational convention defined in Notation 3.1, where a generic partition π is defined with elements T and S, and in which the partition {T1 , T2 } of the set T is defined with |T1 | = |S|. We will write ft1 (y, z) to denote the reaction map of coalition T1 as a function of the vector of strategies xN \T1 in which all members of T2 play y, all the members of S play z, and all players in N \(T ∪ S) play according to the equilibrium profile x(π). Lemma 3.2. Let Assumptions 2.1–2.3 hold. Let π, T, S, T1 and T2 be defined as in Notation 3.1. Then (i) Positive Externalities imply ft1 (xt , xs ) ≤ xt ; (ii) Negative Externalities imply ft1 (xt , xs ) ≥ xt . Proof. Consider first point (i). By definition of xt , for all y ∈ X we write: ut1 ((xt , xt ), xs ) + ut2 ((xt , xt ), xs ) = ut (xt , xs ) ≥ ut (y, xt , xs ) = ut1 ((y, xt ), xs ) + ut2 ((y, xt ), xs ).

(3.19)

Suppose now that ft1 (xt , xs ) > xt . By definition of the map ft1 , we have: ut1 ((ft1 (xt , xs ), xt ), xs ) ≥ ut1 ((xt , xt ), xs ).

(3.20)

Also, by Positive Externalities, we have: ut2 ((ft1 (xt , xt ), xs ) > ut2 ((xt , xt ), xs ).

(3.21)

Equations (3.20) and (3.21) contradict Eq. (3.19). The case of Negative Externalities is proved along similar lines. In particular, suppose that ft1 (xt , xs ) < xt . Equation (3.21) is directly implied, while Eq. (3.20) does not depend on the sign of the externalities. This leads again to a contradiction of (3.19). The desired bound on the slope of reaction maps is imposed by the following contraction assumption, which generalizes to coalitional reaction maps the usual condition imposed in non cooperative games. Assumption 3.1. The game G satisfies the contraction property if for all S and all xN \S the reaction function of S satisfies the following condition: there exists c < 1 such that for all xN \S and xN \S : |fs (xN \S ) − fs (xN \S )| ≤ c · xN \S − xN \S

where · denotes the Euclidean norm in the space Rn−s .

(3.22)

March 23, 2006 10:51 WSPC/151-IGTR

122

00081

S. Currarini & M. A. Marini

Proposition 3.2. Let Assumptions 2.1–2.3 and 3.1 hold. Let π, T, S, T1 and T2 be defined as in Notation 3.1. Then: (i) Positive Externalities imply xs ≤ xt ; (ii) Negative Externalities imply xs ≥ xt . Proof. We first consider the case of Positive Externalities (case (i)). Suppose that, contrary to our statement, |S| ≤ |T | and xs > xt . Assumption 2.1 (symmetry) directly implies xs − xt = ft1 (xt , xt ) − xt

(3.23)

where we have used the definition of the map ft1 introduced before. By Lemma 3.2 we know that Positive Externalities imply: ft1 (xt , xs ) ≤ xt .

(3.24)

Equations (3.23) and (3.24) directly imply that: xs − xt ≤ ft1 (xt , xt ) − ft1 (xt , xs )

(3.25)

where both sides of the inequality are non negative. It is clear that (3.25) violates Assumption 3.1 (contraction) with respect to the map ft1 and to the change of the strategy played by members of S from xt to xs . The case of negative externalities can be proved along similar lines. We again invoke Lemma 3.1 and Proposition 4.7 in Yi (2003) to conclude that Proposition 3.2 directly implies the following theorem. Theorem 3.2. Let Assumptions 2.1–2.3 and 3.1 hold. Then Condition 3.1 holds. This implies that the grand coalition N is a stable coalition structure in the game of coalition formation Γ derived from the game in strategic form G. The results can be summarized as follows: symmetry (in the form of Assumptions 2.1 and 2.2) and the absence of synergies are sufficient conditions for the grand coalition to be a stable coalition structure in the game Γ, provided that reactions maps are not “too decreasing”. 3.1. Example: Cartel formation in oligopoly To illustrate our main results we make use of a game of cartel formation in oligopoly. To keep things simple, let us consider three firms (n = 3), no production costs and the following linear inverse demand function:  qj . (3.26) pi = a − qi − b j=i

The direct demand function is qi = α − βpi + γ

 j=i

pj , with α =

a (n−1)b+1 ,

1−(n−2)b b β = (1−b)((n−1)b+1) and γ = (1−b)((n−1)b+1) . We first study the case of competition in prices, in which strategies are complements (for b ∈ [0, 1]) and the payoff functions satisfy positive externalities. Firms’

March 23, 2006 10:51 WSPC/151-IGTR

00081

Coalition Formation in Games without Synergies

123

payoffs as a function of the price vector p(π) associated with each partition π are as follows: α2 1 , i = 1, 2, 3; ui (p({N })) = 4 (β − 2γ) 1 α2 (2β 2 − βγ − γ 2 )(2β + γ) u1 (p({1, 2}, {3})) = u2 (p({1, 2}, {3})) = ; 4 (2βγ − 2β 2 + γ 2 )2 (3.27) α2 β 3 u3 (p({1, 2}, {3})) = ; (2βγ − 2β 2 + γ 2 )2 1 α2 β ui (p({1}, {2}, {3})) = , i = 1, 2, 3. 4 (β − γ)2 Both positive externalities and increasing differences hold. In the coalition structure ({1, 2} , {3}), both firms in the cartel T = {1, 2} set a Nash equilibrium price αβ+(αγ/2) pt = 2β 2 −2βγ−γ 2 higher, for a > 0 and b ∈ [0, 1), than the smaller coalition S = {3},

αβ setting ps = 2β 2 −2βγ−γ 2 . This fact implies, by Proposition 3.1, that the corresponding equilibrium payoff of each firm in T is lower than that of the firm in S. Numerical simulations confirm this result. Taking for instance a = 1 and b = 14 , we obtain

u1 (p({1, 2}, {3})) = u2 (p({1, 2}, {3})) = .404 95 < .446 27 = u3 (p({1, 2}, {3})). (3.28) To check that the grand coalition is stable, as postulated by Theorem 3.1, note that the equal split monopoly profit ui (p({1, 2, 3})) = .49 is higher than the equally split duopoly profit u1 (p({1, 2}, {3})) = .404 and than the triopoly profit u1 (p({1}, {2}, {3})) = .375. The quantity setting Cournot oligopoly is, instead, a case of negative externalities and strategic substitutability. Let, for simplicity, b = 1. Here, it can be easily checked that the contraction condition assumed in the paper holds. Take a generic coalition structure π with m elements B1 , B2 , . . . , Bm . The equilibrium aggregate quantity produced by each element of π (that is, by each cartel) is: a . (3.29) q(π) = (m + 1) Hence, members of larger cartels produce (each) a smaller quantity than members of smaller cartels, as postulated by Proposition 3.2. Also, since the profit of each firm depends (negatively) on the aggregate production of the market and (positively) on its own production, it follows that firms in smaller cartels (hence producing a larger quantity) gain higher profits than firms in larger cartels (producing a smaller quantity), as postulated by Theorem 3.2. Once again, the grand coalition is a stable coalition structure; indeed, any coalition S of size s, inducing the coalition structure π(S) in which all players outside S split up into singletons, would get a payoff of a2 ui (q(π(S))) = s(n−s+2) 2 , which is smaller than the equally split monopoly profit of 2

a ui (q({N })) = 4n . To complete the illustration of our results, we still need to show that, even under the assumptions of our Theorems 3.1 and 3.2, the existence of synergies in cartel

March 23, 2006 10:51 WSPC/151-IGTR

124

00081

S. Currarini & M. A. Marini

formation can make the monopoly outcome unstable. Let us consider again the Cournot game of cartel formation, and let us introduce a simple form of synergy by assuming, as in Bloch (1997) and Yi (1997), that when firms coordinate their action and create a cartel they can also pool their research assets to develop a new technology in such a way to reduce the cost of each firm in proportion to the number of firms cooperating in the project. We use the following specification of costs: c(qi , si ) = (c + 1 − si)qi , where si is the cardinality of the coalition containing firm i and where, by assumption, a > c ≥ n. As shown by Yi (1997), at the unique Nash equilibrium associated with any arbitrary partition π, the profit of each firm i in a coalition of size si is given by: ui (q(π)) =

2  k a − (n + 1)(c + 1 − si ) + j=1 sj (c + 1 − sj ) (n + 1)2

.

(3.30)

When π = π (S), the profit of each firm i in S reduces to: ui (q(π(S))) =

(a − (n − s + 1)(c + 1 − s) + (n − s)c)2 . (n + 1)2

(3.31)

Although the grand coalition cartel enjoys a very high level of synergy, it turns out that the deviation of a coalition S from the grand coalition is always profitable for: 1 2 1 s>c− n− (n − 4(nc − c2 ) − 8(a − c − 1). 2 2

(3.32)

For example, for n = 8, a deviation by a group of six firms (s = 6) induces a per 2 firm payoff of ui (q(π(S))) = (a−c+15) higher than the per firm payoff in the grand 81 coalition ui (q(N )) =

(a−c+7)2 . 81

Note that in this example Condition 3.1 is violated,

since each firm j outside S obtains as singleton a payoff uj (q(π(S))) = is lower than ui (q(π(S))).

(a−c)2 81

which

4. Concluding Remarks In this paper we have established sufficient conditions for the existence of a stable coalition structure in the coalition unanimity game (or “gamma” game) of coalition formation, as defined by Hart and Kurz (1983). These conditions are directly defined on the strategic form game G used to derive the payoffs in the game of coalition formation. In particular, the absence of synergies is shown to imply the stability of full cooperation if players are symmetric, externalities are monotone and best replies are not “too decreasing”. We think there are potentially interesting extensions of our paper, investigating the conditions on G for the existence of equilibrium in other games of coalition formation such as, for instance, Hart and Kurz’s (1983) delta or “exclusive membership” game, and under alternative equilibrium concepts, such as Ray and Vohra’s (1997) equilibrium binding agreements.

March 23, 2006 10:51 WSPC/151-IGTR

00081

Coalition Formation in Games without Synergies

125

Acknowledgments We thank Francis Bloch for helpful comments and the audiences at the XV Italian Meeting in Game Theory and Applications in Urbino, July 2003 and at the II World Conference in Game Theory in Marseille, July 2004. We also wish to thank two anonymous referees for useful comments. Appendix Proof of Lemma 2.1. We proceed by contradiction. Let S = {1, 2, . . . , s}. Suppose that x∗i = x∗j for some i, j ∈ S. Derive the vector x∗∗ ∈ XS from x∗ by permuting the strategies of players i and j. By symmetry (Assumption 2.1),   ui (x∗∗ ui (x∗S , xN \S ). (A1) S , xN \S ) = i∈S

i∈S

Since the sum of quasiconcave functions is quasiconcave, for all λ ∈ (0, 1) we have:   ∗ ui (λx∗∗ ui (x∗S , xN \S ). (A2) S + (1 − λ)xS , xN \S ) > i∈S

i∈S

∗ Since by convexity of X, the strategy vector (λx∗∗ S + (1 − λ)xS ) ∈ XS , we obtain a contradiction.

Proof of Lemma 2.2. We proceed by contradiction. Let S = {1, 2, . . . , s}. Suppose that x∗i = x∗j for some i, j ∈ S. Symmetry implies that players payoff functions ui (x1 , x2 , . . . , xn ) can be written as a single function: u(x, X),

(A3)

where x is a player’s own strategy and X is the sum of all players’ strategies. Define now the following strategy: 1 (A4) x ˆ ≡ (x∗i + x∗j ). 2 By convexity of X, x ˆ ∈ X. Also,     ∗ ∗ ˆ X = x + x∗ = 2ˆ x+ x∗ + x∗ = X (A5) h

h∈S

h

h∈N \S

h

h∈S\{i,j}

h

h∈N \S

Concavity of u in x implies therefore that: ˆ > u(x∗i , X ∗ ) + u(x∗j , X ∗ ). 2u(ˆ x, X) It follows that ˆ + 2u(ˆ x, X)

 h∈S\{i,j}

ˆ > u(x∗h , X)



u(x∗h , X ∗ ),

(A6)

(A7)

h∈S

which contradicts the assumption that x∗S maximizes the aggregate utility of S given x∗N \S .

March 23, 2006 10:51 WSPC/151-IGTR

126

00081

S. Currarini & M. A. Marini

References Bloch, F. [1997] Non cooperative models of coalition formation in games with spillovers, in New Directions in the Economic Theory of the Environment, eds. Carraro, C. and Siniscalco, D. (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge). Bulow, J., Geanokoplos, J. and Klemperer, P. [1985] Multimarket oligopoly: Strategic substitutes and complements, J. Political Economy 93, 488–511. Currarini, S. and Marini, M. [2004] A conjectural cooperative equilibrium in strategic form games, in Game Practise and the Environment, eds. Carraro, C. and Fragnelli, V. (Cheltenham, U.K. and Northampton, Mass.: Elgar). Hart, S. and Kurz, M. [1983] Endogenous formation of coalitions, Econometrica 52, 1047–1064. Ray, D. and Vohra, R. [1997] Equilibrium binding agreement, J. Economic Theory 73, 30–78. von Neumann J. and Morgenstern, O. [1944] Theory of Games and Economic Behaviour (Princeton University Press, Princeton). Yi, S.-S. [1997] Stable coalition structure with externalities, Games and Economic Behaviour 20, 201–237. Yi, S.-S. [2003] The endogenous formation of economic coalitions: The partition function approach, in The Endogenous Formation of Economic Coalitions, ed. Carraro, C. (Fondazione Enrico Mattei Series in Economics and the Environment, Cheltenham, U.K. and Northampton, Mass.: Elgar).

March 23, 2006 10:51 WSPC/151-IGTR 00081 ...

Universit`a degli Studi di Urbino “Carlo Bo”, Italy and London School of Economics, UK [email protected]. This paper establishes sufficient conditions for ...

247KB Sizes 0 Downloads 225 Views

Recommend Documents

CS636-2006S-MID Midterm March 23, 2006 Name
This exam is open text and notes. However, you may NOT share material with another student during the exam. Be concise and clearly indicate your answer.

28 March 2006 - Sites
But I can make my theory of Magical. Medicine completely consistent with the evidence (like a conspiracy theory). • e.g. I ascribe different maladies to the.

1051.pdf
and occurs during surgery and general anaesthesia with. mechanical ... and electrolytes pass out of the circulation into the inter- stitium. As the volume .... sample can then be calculated. Similar ... Intermediate-sized fluid volumes (12.5 to.

2014 03 23 Newsletter March 23 2014.pdf
the celebration of the Lord's Passion. Holy Saturday (9.00pm): Take part in the Entrance. Procession and help light candles during the service of light. To respond to the call, please contact Fr. Aidan 087-6397744 or. Bridget Breen 086-1762532. Evang

NSE/CD/32061 Date : March 23, 2016
Mar 23, 2016 - Members are requested not to transfer any data files for ... Kindly participate actively in the mock trading session from all trading software and re- ... NEAT-CDS TWS entry in the „Programs‟ sub-menu of the „Start‟ menu. c.

March 23 Alert SBI.pdf
Action Five: Social Media. Twitter: Access your member of Congress' twitter handle at http://stuffthought.com/blog/113th-congress-twitter-handles/. Sample ...

NSE/CD/32061 Date : March 23, 2016
Mar 23, 2016 - Members are requested not to transfer any data files for ... Download the setup file „NEATCDTWSSetup.exe‟ to your hard disc in the root.

arXiv:cs.CY/0511005 v2 23 Aug 2006
Indiana University ... discussed in computer, social and political science [14, 24, ... Since i is ranked highly by the search engine, it has a high probability of being ...

arXiv:hep-th/0610241 v1 23 Oct 2006
We prove that the full Lagrangian (in Euclidean signature) of the standard model minimally coupled .... Barrett [4] with a solution of the fermion doubling problem. The first ... The ALR-bimodule MF = E⊕E0 is the direct sum of the bimodule. (2.4).

October 23, 2006 17:23 WSPC/123-JCSC 00318 ...
role, especially in global interconnect systems, where large buffers drive long global ..... Mis i . (9). Substituting (9) into (8) and equating like powers of s, we have.

(March 2006) The Rise and Fall of SPRE.pdf
There was a problem previewing this document. Retrying... Download. Connect more apps... Try one of the apps below to open or edit this item. (March 2006) ...

1 Craig Napolitano Anthrax Summary March 2, 2006 ...
receptor-mediated, clathrin-dependent, endocytosis into an acidic vesicle. ... LF, containing an amino acid change from glutamate 687 → cysteine 687, was ...

Audit Report - 31st March, 2006.pdf
Page 3 of 60. 3. INDICE. Sinopsis ....................................................................................................................................5. Capítulo 1 .....................................................................

Audit Report - 31st March, 2006.pdf
There was a problem previewing this document. Retrying... Download. Connect more apps... Audit Report ... rch, 2006.pdf. Audit Report - ... arch, 2006.pdf. Open.

Found in Translation, Sojourners Magazine/March 2006
Mar 23, 2006 - back to online version .... Its etymology (the root miss means “send”) reminds us that God .... Phone: (202) 328-8842 • Fax: (202) 328-8757.

Minutes March 9-10, 2006.pdf
Main Office (360) 725-6275 ○ FAX (360) 586-4548 ○ http://www.pesb.wa.gov ... Education of the Deaf to receive an endorsement in Washington without taking ...

Minutes of the CHMP meeting 20-23 March 2017 - European ...
May 4, 2017 - Re-examination of initial application procedures under Article 9(2) of ...... scientific advice given to companies during the development of ...

NSE/CML/34454 Date : March 23, 2017 Circular Re
Mar 23, 2017 - In pursuance of Regulation 3.1.1 of the National Stock Exchange (Capital ... For the purpose of trading on the system, the security shall be ...

NSE/CML/37285 Date : March 23, 2018 Circular Ref
Mar 23, 2018 - Sub: Revocation of suspension of trading in units - on account of Interval Scheme - UTI. Mutual Fund. It is hereby notified that the suspension of ...

PDCO minutes 20-23 March 2018 - European Medicines Agency
Mar 23, 2018 - 10. 2.1.8. Tenofovir Alafenamide / Emtricitabine - EMEA-001577-PIP03-17 . ...... patients from 6 months to less than 18 years old.

NSE/CML/37285 Date : March 23, 2018 Circular Ref
Mar 23, 2018 - Mutual Fund. It is hereby notified that the suspension of trading in the following securities will be revoked w.e.f. March. 26, 2018 based on confirmation submitted by UTI Asset Management Company Limited regarding continuation of the

NSE/CML/34451 Date : March 23, 2017 Circular Re
Mar 23, 2017 - ANNEXURE. 1. Adani Power Limited. Symbol. ADANIPOWER. Name of the Company. Adani Power Limited. Series. EQ. ISIN*. INE814H01011.

FBI HQ 23 March 2018.pdf
Mar 23, 2018 - This is the antithesis of our United States of America and Democracy. I need help immediately or this intelligence community will kill me. Benjamin Allen Sullivan. http://www.basrc.biz/help. Email Address as stated on the. business car

Simplify, Refocus & Coordinate, CAP March 2006.pdf
There was a problem loading this page. Retrying... Simplify, Refocus & Coordinate, CAP March 2006.pdf. Simplify, Refocus & Coordinate, CAP March 2006.pdf.