Group Incentive Compatibility for Matching with Contracts John William Hatfield and Fuhito Kojima∗ October 27, 2008

Abstract Hatfield and Milgrom (2005) present a unified model of matching with contracts, which includes the standard two-sided matching and some package auction models as special cases. They show that the doctor-optimal stable mechanism is strategy-proof for doctors if hospitals’ preferences satisfy substitutes and the law of aggregate demand. We show that the doctor-optimal stable mechanism is group strategy-proof for doctors under these same conditions. That is, no group of doctors can make each of its members strictly better off by jointly misreporting their preferences. We derive as a corollary of this result that no individually rational allocation is preferred by all the doctors to the doctor-optimal stable allocation. Journal of Economic Literature Classification Numbers: C78, D44. Key Words: matching, matching with contracts, substitutes, law of aggregate demand, stability, strategy-proofness, group strategyproofness.

1

Introduction

The theory of two-sided matching markets has interested researchers for its theoretical appeal and its relevance to the design of real-world institutions. The medical residency matching mechanism in the U.S. (National Residency Matching Program) and student assignment systems in New York City and ∗

Hatfield: Graduate School of Business, Stanford University, Stanford, CA 94305, email: hatfield [email protected]. Kojima: Cowles Foundation, Yale University, New Haven, CT 06510, e-mail: [email protected]. We are grateful to Paul Milgrom and Al Roth as well as the editor and anonymous referees for comments.

1

Boston (among others) are examples of mechanisms designed by economists using the theory.1 Hatfield and Milgrom (2005) present a unified framework of matching with contracts, which includes the two-sided matching models and package auction models as special cases. They introduce the substitutes condition of contracts, which generalizes the substitutability condition in the matching literature (Roth and Sotomayor, 1990). They also introduce a new condition they call the law of aggregate demand, which states that hospitals choose more contracts as the set of contracts to choose from expands. They show that the doctor-optimal stable mechanism is strategy-proof for doctors if hospitals’ preferences satisfy substitutes and the law of aggregate demand. That is, no single doctor is made strictly better off by misreporting her preferences. We show that this same mechanism is in fact group strategy-proof for doctors. That is, no group of doctors can make each of its members strictly better off by jointly misreporting their preferences. Under the substitutes condition, the law of aggregate demand is essentially the weakest possible sufficient condition for group strategy-proofness (or even strategy-proofness).2 The many previous results on strategy-proofness and group strategy-proofness (Dubins and Freedman, 1981; Roth, 1982; Martinez et al., 2004; Abdulkadiro˘glu, 2005; Hatfield and Milgrom, 2005) are special cases of this result. Furthermore, it is well-known that for the doctor-optimal stable mechanism a group of doctors can deviate in such a way to make some members strictly better off and none worse off (Dubins and Freedman, 1981) and that the mechanism is not even strategy-proof for hospitals (Roth, 1982). As an application of our main result, we show a welfare result known as “weak Pareto optimality.” More specifically, if preferences of every hospital satisfy substitutes and the law of aggregate demand, then there exists no individually rational allocation that every doctor strictly prefers to the doctor-optimal stable allocation. This result has been shown by a number of studies under various assumptions (Roth, 1982; Martinez et al., 2004; Kojima, 2007). 1

The theory was pioneered by Gale and Shapley (1962). For applications to labor markets, see Roth (1984) and Roth and Peranson (1999). For applications to student assignment, see for example Abdulkadiro˘glu and S¨onmez (2003), Abdulkadiro˘glu, Pathak and Roth (2005) and Abdulkadiro˘ glu, Pathak, Roth and S¨onmez (2005). 2 Theorem 12 of Hatfield and Milgrom (2005) presents a sense in which the law of aggregate demand is “essentially the weakest” sufficient condition for strategy-proofness of the doctor-optimal stable mechanism. Explaining the theorem, they write “to the extent that the law of aggregate demand for hospital preferences has observable consequences for the progress of the doctor-offering algorithm, it is an indispensable condition to ensure the dominant strategy property for doctors.” For a more precise statement of their result, see footnote 3.

2

In addition to its theoretical appeal, our results have interesting implications for the various applications of matching models, especially those regarding school choice (Abdulkadiro˘glu and S¨onmez, 2003). Focusing on strategic behavior and welfare of students is natural in the school choice setting, since school priorities are often set by the law and manipulations by schools are impossible, and schools are regarded as objects whose priorities are not taken into account in welfare consideration. The generality of our preferences is important, since school priorities often violate assumptions under which the incentive and welfare conclusions have been shown in the literature. Some of the public schools in the New York City are, for example, required to admit a balanced mix of students from high, middle and low test score populations (Abdulkadiro˘glu et al., 2005). Such requirements can easily be seen to violate the previous conditions, but still satisfy substitutes and the law of aggregate demand. Thus our analysis gives some additional justification for the use of the student-optimal stable mechanism originally advocated by Balinski and S¨onmez (1999) and Abdulkadiro˘glu and S¨onmez (2003).

2

Model

There are finite sets D and H of doctors and hospitals. X is the set of contracts. Each contract x ∈ X is bilateral, so that it is associated with a doctor xD ∈ D and a hospital xH ∈ H. We assume that each doctor can sign at most one contract. The null contract, meaning that the doctor has no contract, is denoted by ∅. For each d ∈ D, Pd is a strict preference relation on {x ∈ X|xD = d} ∪ {∅}. A contract is acceptable if it is preferred to the null contract and unacceptable if it is not preferred to the null contract. For each d ∈ D and X 0 ⊂ X, we define the chosen set Cd by  ∅ if all x ∈ X 0 such that xD = d are unacceptable to d, 0 Cd (X ) = maxPd {x ∈ X 0 |xD = d} otherwise, S for any X 0 ⊂ X. Let CD (X 0 ) = d∈D Cd (X 0 ) be the set of contracts chosen from X 0 by some doctor. We allow each hospital to sign multiple contracts, and assume that each hospital h ∈ H has a preference relation Ph on subsets of contracts involving it. For any X 0 ⊂ X, define Ch (X 0 ) by Ch (X 0 ) = max{X 00 ⊂ X 0 |x ∈ X 00 ⇒ xH = h and x, x0 ∈ X 00 , x 6= x0 ⇒ xD 6= x0D }. Ph

Let CH (X 0 ) = hospital.

S

h∈H

Ch (X 0 ) be the set of contracts chosen from X 0 by some

3

We write P = (Pd )d∈D to denote a preference profile of doctors. We also write P−d to denote (Pd0 )d0 6=d for d ∈ D, and PD0 to denote (Pd )d∈D0 and P−D0 0 to denote (Pd )d∈D / 0 for D ⊂ D. 0 A set of contracts X ⊂ X is an allocation if x, x0 ∈ X 0 and x 6= x0 imply xD 6= x0D . In words, a set of contracts is an allocation if each doctor signs at most one contract. Definition 1. A set of contracts X 0 ⊂ X is a stable allocation (or a stable set of contracts) if 1. CD (X 0 ) = CH (X 0 ) = X 0 , and 2. there exists no hospital h and set of contracts X 00 6= Ch (X 0 ) such that X 00 = Ch (X 0 ∪ X 00 ) ⊂ CD (X 0 ∪ X 00 ). When condition (2) is violated by some X 00 , we say that X 00 is a blocking set for X 0 . For any X 0 ⊂ X and h ∈ H, define the rejected set by Rh (X 0 ) = X 0 − Ch (X 0 ). Rh (X 0 ) is the set of contracts in X 0 which h is willing to reject. Definition 2. Contracts are substitutes for h if we have Rh (X 0 ) ⊂ Rh (X 00 ) for all X 0 ⊂ X 00 ⊂ X. Hatfield and Milgrom (2005) show that there exists a stable set of contracts when contracts are substitutes for every hospital. Result 1 (Hatfield and Milgrom 2005). Suppose that contracts are substitutes for every hospital. Then there exists a stable set of contracts. Moreover, there exists a stable allocation which every doctor weakly prefers to any other stable allocation. A stable allocation which every doctor weakly prefers to any other stable allocation is called the doctor-optimal stable allocation. A mechanism is a mapping F from the set of preference profiles to the set of allocations. The doctor-optimal stable mechanism is a mechanism which, for any reported preference profile P , produces the doctor-optimal stable allocation under P . Hatfield and Milgrom (2005) also introduce the law of aggregate demand, which is the key condition for the doctor-optimal stable mechanism to be strategy-proof. Definition 3. The preferences of hospital h ∈ H satisfy the law of aggregate demand if for all X 0 ⊂ X 00 ⊂ X, |Ch (X 0 )| ≤ |Ch (X 00 )|.

4

A mechanism F is strategy-proof if, for any preference profile P , there is no doctor d and preferences Pd0 such that d strictly prefers yd to xd according to Pd , where xd and yd are the (possibly null) contracts for d in F (P ) and F ((Pd0 , P−d )), respectively. Result 2 (Hatfield and Milgrom 2005). Suppose that preferences of every hospital satisfy substitutes and the law of aggregate demand. Then the doctoroptimal stable mechanism is strategy-proof. A mechanism F is group strategy-proof if, for any preference profile P , there is no group of doctors D0 ⊂ D and a preference profile PD0 0 = (Pd0 )d∈D0 such that every d ∈ D0 strictly prefers yd to xd according to Pd , where xd and yd are the (possibly null) contracts for d in F (P ) and F ((PD0 0 , P−D0 )), respectively.

3

Result

We build on and extend Result 2 by Hatfield and Milgrom (2005) to obtain the following main result. To do this, we first show the following lemma: Lemma 1. Let Z be the doctor-optimal stable allocation under preference profile P . Let d obtain z ∈ Z and suppose that y is preferred to z under Pd . Let Pd0 be the preference ordering where y is ranked first by d and is otherwise unchanged from Pd . Then the doctor-optimal stable allocation for the preference profile (Pd0 , P−d ) is Z. Proof. Z is stable under (Pd0 , P−d ) as if any blocking set Y 0 existed, Y 0 would block Z under P , as the set of contracts preferred by the doctors to their contract in Z is unchanged. Now suppose that another allocation, Y , is stable under (Pd0 , P−d ). If y∈ / Y , then the set Y 0 that blocks Y under P also blocks Y under (Pd0 , P−d ). If y ∈ Y , then the doctor-optimal stable mechanism would not be strategyproof, violating Result 2. Hence Z is the doctor-optimal stable allocation under (Pd0 , P−d ). We now state and prove the main result. Theorem 1. Suppose that preferences of every hospital satisfy substitutes and the law of aggregate demand. Then the doctor-optimal stable mechanism is group strategy-proof.

5

Proof. Suppose by way of contradiction that doctors’ true preferences are given by the preference profile P , and suppose there exists a coalition D0 that can profitably misreport its members’ preferences. Let {zd }d∈D0 be the set of contracts doctors in D0 obtain when they report their true preferences PD0 and {yd }d∈D0 those they obtain when they report false preferences PˆD0 such that every d ∈ D0 strictly prefers yd to zd under Pd . Finally, let Y be the outcome of the doctor-optimal stable mechanism for the report (PˆD0 , P−D0 ), and Z the outcome of the doctor-optimal stable mechanism for the report P . Let Pd0 be the preferences of d in which yd is the most preferred contract and the ranking of every other contract is identical to Pd . Since yd is d’s first choice under Pd0 for each d ∈ D0 , Y is stable under (PD0 0 , P−D0 ) as it was stable under (PˆD0 , P−D0 ) and there are now fewer possible blocking coalitions of Y . Hence, because the doctor-optimal stable allocation is weakly most preferred by every doctor amongst all stable allocations, each d ∈ D0 must obtain yd as part of the doctor-optimal stable allocation under (PD0 0 , P−D0 ). Now consider the outcome of the doctor-optimal stable mechanism for 0 (Pd , P−d ) for some d ∈ D0 . By Lemma 1, the doctor-optimal stable allocation for these preferences must be Z. Iterating this result for each agent in D0 , the doctor-optimal stable allocation for (PD0 0 , P−D0 ) must be Z. But this contradicts our result in the previous paragraph that the doctor-optimal stable mechanism under (PD0 0 , P−D0 ) must provide yd for each d ∈ D0 . Many incentive compatibility results in the literature are special cases of Theorem 1. Strategy-proofness was first obtained by Dubins and Freedman (1981) and Roth (1982) in one-to-one matching markets without contracts, and extended by Abdulkadiro˘glu (2005) to more general preferences and then by Hatfield and Milgrom (2005) to the matching markets with contracts under the substitutes and the law of aggregate demand conditions. Group strategy-proofness was first shown by Dubins and Freedman (1981) in one-to-one matching without contracts. Martinez et al. (2004) obtained group strategy-proofness in many-to-one matching without contracts when hospitals’ preferences satisfy substitutes and what they call q-separability, a condition stronger than the law of aggregate demand. All these results are special cases of Theorem 1. The proof presented is also more straightforward than the previous ones in the literature. For example, the proof in Martinez et al. (2004) refers to a technical result (the Blocking Lemma of Gale and Sotomayor (1985) adapted to their environment), which is proved in a separate full-length paper (Martinez et al., 2006). Here we simply build upon the previous strategyproofness result. The key insight is that if a deviation by a group can make all members of that group strictly better off, then there exists a specification 6

of preferences such that one agent can make herself strictly better off by a false report. A natural question is whether Theorem 1 can be further generalized. Within preferences satisfying the substitutes condition, Hatfield and Milgrom (2005) show that the law of aggregate demand is essentially the weakest possible condition to guarantee strategy-proofness.3 Since group strategyproofness is a stronger property than strategy-proofness, their result implies the same conclusion for group strategy-proofness. Another possible extension of this result is the claim that no coalition of doctors can misreport preferences and make some of its members strictly better off without making any of its members strictly worse off. Unfortunately, such a result does not hold even in one-to-one matching markets (Dubins and Freedman, 1981).4 This fact suggests that, while outside the model, it may be possible for a coalition of doctors to manipulate the doctor-optimal stable mechanism if even small transfers are allowed among doctors: for the application of our results to problems in, say, auction design, this is a substantial limitation. See section 4.3.1. of Roth and Sotomayor (1990) for exposition and discussion of this point. Furthermore, Theorem 1 can not be further generalized to include coalitions including hospitals. In one-to-one matching markets, it is well-known that a hospital can improve its outcome by not reporting truthfully under the doctor-optimal stable mechanism (Roth, 1982). Further, in many-toone matching markets, even a single hospital can sometimes manipulate the 3 As shown in Theorem 12 of Hatfield and Milgrom (2005), if there exists a violation of the law of aggregate demand such that there are three contracts x, y, z and set of contracts X 0 such that yD 6= zD 6= xD 6= yD and y, z ∈ Rh (X 0 ∪ {x}) − Rh (X 0 ), and one other hospital, then there exist preferences for the doctors and singleton preferences for the other hospital such that the mechanism is not strategy-proof for the doctors. 4 A simple example below shows that a stronger version of the group strategy-proofness as stated in the main text does not hold. Let each hospital find only singleton sets of contracts acceptable, and preferences of doctors d, d0 , d00 and hospitals h, h0 be:

Pd : (d, h0 ), (d, h)

Ph : (d, h), (d0 , h), (d00 , h)

Pd0 : (d0 , h) 00

Ph0 : (d00 , h0 ), (d, h0 ) 00

0

Pd00 : (d , h), (d , h ) where the above notation is understood to mean that d prefers contract (d, h0 ) best and (d, h) second and the null contract third, and so on. Then the doctor-optimal stable allocation is {(d, h), (d00 , h0 )}. However, if d0 were to report that no contract is acceptable and d and d00 report Pd0 and Pd00 respectively, then the doctor-optimal stable mechanism results in allocation {(d, h0 ), (d00 , h)}, which every doctor weakly prefers and doctors d and d00 strictly prefer to {(d, h), (d00 , h0 )}.

7

hospital-optimal stable mechanism (Roth, 1985). Interestingly, the doctor-optimal stable mechanism is both group strategyproof and, from the perspective of the doctors, bossy, that is, a doctor can change her preferences and change the allocation without changing her own outcome.5 This observation may look contradictory to the well-known result (see Lemma 1 of Papai (2000)) that group strategy-proofness is equivalent to strategy-proofness and nonbossiness in models such as the house allocation problem (Shapley and Scarf, 1974; Hylland and Zeckhauser, 1979). This is not a contradiction, however, since nonbossiness and strategy-proofness are equivalent to a stronger claim that no group can misreport in such a way that some agent in the group is made strictly better off while no one in the group is made strictly worse off. Our result can also be used to derive another result that has been proven before in a number of special contexts. An immediate corollary of Theorem 1 is the following welfare result. Corollary 1. Suppose that preferences of every hospital satisfy substitutes and the law of aggregate demand. Then there exists no individually rational allocation that every doctor strictly prefers to the doctor-optimal stable allocation. Proof. Suppose by way of contradiction that there is an individually rational allocation {yd }d∈D that each doctor strictly prefers to the doctor-optimal stable allocation. For each d ∈ D, let Pd0 be preferences that declare yd as the unique acceptable contract. It is easy to show that {yd }d∈D is the unique stable allocation when each d declares Pd0 . This contradicts Theorem 1, completing the proof. The result is known as “weak Pareto optimality” in the literature and first presented by Roth (1982) for one-to-one matching. Martinez et al. (2004) obtain the result in many-to-one matching when hospitals’ preferences satisfy substitutes and q-separability. Kojima (2007) gives a direct proof of Corollary 1 except that he does not consider matching with contracts and focuses on the simpler many-to-one setting without contracts.

4

Concluding Remarks

The matching problem with contracts subsumes a large class of problems, such as the matching model with fixed terms of contract, the job matching 5

An example in footnote 4 is an environment where nonbossiness is violated by the doctor-optimal stable mechanism.

8

model with adjustable wages of Kelso and Crawford (1982) and the package auction model of Ausubel and Milgrom (2002). The current paper shows that the substitutes condition and the law of aggregate demand are sufficient for group strategy-proofness and the weak Pareto optimality property. We note an interesting coincidence of maximal domains for strategyproofness and group strategy-proofness. Hatfield and Milgrom (2005) show that, under the substitutes condition, the law of aggregate demand is essentially the weakest condition to ensure strategy-proofness, and by implication the same is true for group strategy-proofness. It is more surprising, however, that the more demanding group strategy-proofness property holds under the same set of assumptions.

References Abdulkadiro˘ glu, Atila, “College Admission with Affirmative Action,” International Journal of Game Theory, 2005, 33, 535–549. and Tayfun S¨ onmez, “School Choice: A Mechanism Design Approach,” American Economic Review, 2003, 93, 729–747. , Parag A. Pathak, Alvin E. Roth, and Tayfun S¨ onmez, “The Boston Public School Match,” American Economic Review Papers and Proceedings, 2005, 95, 368–372. , , and , “The New York City High School Match,” American Economic Review Papers and Proceedings, 2005, 95, 364–367. Ausubel, Lawrence M. and Paul R. Milgrom, “Ascending Auctions with Package Bidding,” Frontiers of Theoretical Economics, 2002, 1, 1. Balinski, Michel and Tayfun S¨ onmez, “A tale of two mechanisms: student placement,” Journal of Economic Theory, 1999, 84, 73–94. Dubins, L. E. and D. A. Freedman, “Machiavelli and the Gale-Shapley algorithm,” American Mathematical Monthly, 1981, 88, 485–494. Gale, David and Lloyd S. Shapley, “College Admissions and the Stability of Marriage,” American Mathematical Monthly, 1962, 69, 9–15. and Marilda A. Oliveira Sotomayor, “Some remarks on the stable matching problem,” Discrete Applied Mathematics, 1985, 11, 223–232.

9

Hatfield, John William and Paul R. Milgrom, “Matching with Contracts,” American Economic Review, 2005, 95, 913–935. Hylland, Aanund and Richard Zeckhauser, “The Efficient Allocation of Individuals to Positions,” Journal of Political Economy, 1979, 87, 293–314. Kelso, Alexander and Vincent P. Crawford, “Job matching, coalition formation, and gross substitutes,” Econometrica, 1982, 50, 1483–1504. Kojima, Fuhito, “The Law of Aggregate Demand and Welfare in the TwoSided Matching Market,” 2007. forthcoming, Economics Letters. Martinez, Ruth, Jordi Masso, Alejandro Neme, and Jorge Oviedo, “On group strategy-proof mechanisms for a many-to-one matching model,” International Journal of Game Theory, 2004, 33, 115–128. , , , and , “The Blocking Lemma for a Many-to-one Maching Model,” 2006. mimeo. Papai, Szilvia, “Strategyproof Assignment by Hierarchical Exchange,” Econometrica, 2000, 68, 1403–1433. Roth, Alvin E., “The Economics of Matching: Stability and Incentives,” Mathematics of Operations Research, 1982, 7, 617–628. , “The Evolution of the Labor Market for Medical Interns and Residents: A Case Study in Game Theory,” Journal of Political Economy, 1984, 92, 991–1016. , “The college admission problem is not equivalent to the marriage problem,” Journal of Economic Theory, 1985, 36, 277–288. and Elliott Peranson, “The Redesign of the Matching Market for American Physicians: Some Engineering Aspects of Economic Design,” American Economic Review, 1999, 89, 748–780. and Marilda A. O. Sotomayor, Two-sided matching: a study in gametheoretic modeling and analysis, Cambridge: Econometric Society monographs, 1990. Shapley, Lloyd and Herbert Scarf, “On Cores and Indivisibility,” Journal of Mathematical Economics, 1974, 1, 23–37.

10

Group Incentive Compatibility for Matching with ... - Semantic Scholar

Oct 27, 2008 - to a technical result (the Blocking Lemma of Gale and Sotomayor .... Abdulkadiro˘glu, Atila, “College Admission with Affirmative Action,” In-.

151KB Sizes 0 Downloads 239 Views

Recommend Documents

Group Incentive Compatibility for Matching with Contracts
Oct 27, 2008 - Matching Program) and student assignment systems in New York City ... incentive and welfare conclusions have been shown in the literature.

Group incentive compatibility for matching with contracts
Jan 30, 2009 - (2004) refers to a technical result (the Blocking Lemma of Gale and Sotomayor, 1985, adapted to .... College admission with affirmative action.

Mechanism Design with Weaker Incentive Compatibility Constraints1
Jun 13, 2005 - Game Theory. The MIT Press, Cambridge/London. [4] Green, J. R., Laffont, J.J., 1986. Partially verifiable information and mechanism design.

Mechanism Design with Weaker Incentive Compatibility Constraints1
Jun 13, 2005 - grateful to my advisors Jeff Ely and Michael Whinston. I also thank Paul Beaudry and two anonymous referees for helpful comments. 2Department of Economics, The University of British Columbia, #997-1873 East Mall, Vancouver,. BC, V6T 1Z

Fast exact string matching algorithms - Semantic Scholar
LITIS, Faculté des Sciences et des Techniques, Université de Rouen, 76821 Mont-Saint-Aignan Cedex, France ... Available online 26 January 2007 ... the Karp–Rabin algorithm consists in computing h(x). ..... programs have been compiled with gcc wit

Time Warping-Based Sequence Matching for ... - Semantic Scholar
The proliferation of digital video urges the need of ... proposed an ordinal signature generated by ... and temporal signature matching, which obtains better.

Time Warping-Based Sequence Matching for ... - Semantic Scholar
The proliferation of digital video urges the need of video copy detection for content and rights management. An efficient video copy detection technique should be able to deal with spatiotemporal variations (e.g., changes in brightness or frame rates

Towards High-performance Pattern Matching on ... - Semantic Scholar
such as traffic classification, application identification and intrusion prevention. In this paper, we ..... OCTEON Software Developer Kit (Cavium SDK version 1.5):.

Manipulability in Matching Markets: Conflict and ... - Semantic Scholar
Jun 14, 2010 - Consider the following matching market with students s1,s2,s3, and s4, and colleges c1 and c2. ... American Economic Review, 99(3): 608-627.

Towards High-performance Pattern Matching on ... - Semantic Scholar
1Department of Automation, Tsinghua University, Beijing, 100084, China. ... of-art 16-MIPS-core network processing platform and evaluated with real-life data ...

Manipulability in Matching Markets: Conflict and ... - Semantic Scholar
Jun 14, 2010 - ... research fellowship from Harvard Business School and support from Plan ..... for a college c with preferences Pc over individual students, P′.

3DNN: Viewpoint Invariant 3D Geometry Matching ... - Semantic Scholar
Google Inc. ∗ [email protected]. Martial Hebert ... Neighbor), which is capable of matching an image with 3D data, independently of the ... computer vision field. Researchers have ... match an input image (or patches of an image) with a cor-.

Incentive Compatibility of Bitcoin Mining Pool Reward ...
H contains for each miner i the total number of shares bi ∈ N that have been reported in ... We define three properties which are important for a reward function.

Anesthesia for ECT - Semantic Scholar
Nov 8, 2001 - Successful electroconvulsive therapy (ECT) requires close collaboration between the psychiatrist and the anaes- thetist. During the past decades, anaesthetic techniques have evolved to improve the comfort and safety of administration of

Multi-Group Random Access Resource Allocation ... - Semantic Scholar
J.-W. Choi (corresponding author) is with the Department of Informa- tion & Communication Engineering, Daegu ..... SIR (dB). Probability. Group 1 @ Underlay P1=1.0000P1. Group 2 @ Underlay P2=0.1975P1. Group 3 @ Underlay P3=0.0672P1. Group 1 @ Overla

Group identity and relation-specific investment An ... - Semantic Scholar
Nov 21, 2012 - ... of inefficiency in a world of incomplete contracts, and the central theme of ... We add to the literature by experimentally investigating group ...

Estimating Anthropometry with Microsoft Kinect - Semantic Scholar
May 10, 2013 - Anthropometric measurement data can be used to design a variety of devices and processes with which humans will .... Each Kinect sensor was paired with a dedicated ..... Khoshelham, K. (2011), Accuracy analysis of kinect.

Optimal Allocation Mechanisms with Single ... - Semantic Scholar
Oct 18, 2010 - [25] Milgrom, P. (1996): “Procuring Universal Service: Putting Auction Theory to Work,” Lecture at the Royal Academy of Sciences. [26] Myerson ...

Group identity and relation-specific investment An ... - Semantic Scholar
a School of Economics, Australian School of Business, University of New South Wales, Australia ... Available online 21 November 2012 ... game with either a member of their own team (representing integration) or a member of the other team ...... if th

PY/ED 511: Alternative Strategies for Working with ... - Semantic Scholar
Office: Campion 201A Tel: 552-0670. Office Hours: Friday, 3-5 pm, Professor Suardi; Wednesday, 3-5 pm,. Professor ... Diane Dujon, Judy Gradford, and Dottie Stevens, pp. 281-288;. Beyond Racial Identity Politics: Towards a Liberation Theory for. Mult

Almost Tight Bounds for Rumour Spreading with ... | Semantic Scholar
May 28, 2010 - The result is almost tight because Ω(log n/φ) is a lower bound2 — in particular, the bound is .... probability that i calls j in any given round. They show ...... new node (that is, to the center of the large star), will be O(φ).