*Title Page

Evidence for benefits of argumentation in a Mayan indigenous population Thomas Castelain1,2,3, Vittorio Girotto4, Frank Jamet5, Hugo Mercier1,2*

Affiliations: 1

Centre de Sciences Cognitives, Université de Neuchâtel, Switzerland.

2

Institut des Sciences Cognitives - Marc Jeannerod, L2C2, Centre National de la Recherche

Scientifique, France. 3

Instituto de Investigaciones Psicológicas, Universidad de Costa Rica, Costa Rica.

4

Center for Experimental Research in Management and Economics, DCP, University IUAV

of Venice, Italy. 5

Chart- Cognitions humaine et artificielle, Université de Cergy-Pontoise, France.

*Correspondence to: , Switzerland. E-mail: [email protected].

Keywords: Reasoning, argumentation, myside bias, traditional populations. Word count: 4336

*Manuscript Click here to view linked References

1

Evidence for benefits of argumentation in a Mayan indigenous population

2 3

Keywords: Reasoning, argumentation, myside bias, traditional populations.

4

Word count: 4336

5

6

Abstract

7

Group discussion improves on individual reasoning performance for a wide variety of tasks.

8

This improvement, however, could be largely specific to members of modern, schooled,

9

affluent Western cultures. In two studies, we observed the same improvement in the members

10

of a traditional population—indigenous Maya from Guatemala. Two features of reasoning can

11

account for this improvement: the myside bias, which precludes individuals from improving

12

their performance on their own, and the ability to soundly evaluate others’ arguments, which

13

allows individuals to benefit from group discussions. These two features were observed in the

14

traditional population studied: solitary reasoning performance was marked by the myside

15

bias; individuals were more likely to be convinced by arguments for the correct answer rather

16

than for a wrong answer. Together with previous evidence, the present results strengthen the

17

conclusion that these features are adaptive features of reasoning.

2

18

At least since Descartes, reasoning has generally been understood as a tool of

19

individual cognition: by carefully evaluating and weighing one’s reasons, one should arrive at

20

sounder beliefs and better decisions (Descartes, 1637; Kahneman, 2003; Stanovich, 2004).

21

Opposed to this individualistic view, an alternative is that reasoning’s main function is social:

22

to find reasons in order to convince others, and to evaluate others’ reasons in order to adopt

23

better supported beliefs. The argumentative theory of reasoning (Mercier & Sperber, 2011) is

24

a recent instantiation of this social view of reasoning (for other social views of reasoning, see

25

Baumeister & Masicampo, 2010; Billig, 1996; Gibbard, 1990; Piaget, 1928).

26

An important result supporting the argumentative theory of reasoning is that, provided

27

minimal conditions are met (e.g. the expression of disagreement, see Janis, 1982),

28

argumentation in the course of group discussion produces sizeable improvements in reasoning

29

performance on a variety of tasks, such as logical, mathematical, and inductive problems

30

(Laughlin, 2011; Moshman & Geil, 1998; Trouche, Sander, & Mercier, 2014), work related

31

tasks (Mercier, 2011c), forecasting (Mellers et al., 2014; Rowe & Wright, 1999), and school

32

tasks (Mercier, 2011b; Slavin, 1995; Smith et al., 2009). The argumentative theory suggests

33

that the gap in performance between individual reasoning and reasoning in discussion stems

34

from a combination of two features of reasoning. The first is the myside bias (or confirmation

35

bias): individuals overwhelming produce reasons for their preferred opinions (Mercier, in

36

pressa; Nickerson, 1998). As a result, reasoning rarely allows the lone reasoner to correct

37

mistaken intuitions. Instead, the myside bias can lead to overconfidence (Koriat, Lichtenstein,

38

& Fischhoff, 1980) and polarization (Tesser & Conlee, 1975). The second feature is

39

reasoning’s ability to soundly evaluate others’ arguments, rejecting weak arguments and

40

accepting strong enough ones (Hahn & Oaksford, 2007; Petty & Wegener, 1998). In a

41

discussion group members only provide arguments for their side, but they also evaluate each

3

42

other’s arguments. They change their minds when the arguments are good enough, which

43

usually means changing their mind for the best.

44

These features of reasoning, along with the gap in reasoning performance they seek to

45

explain, could be a peculiarity of WEIRD (Western Educated Industrialized Rich Democratic)

46

cultures. These cultures, in which the research mentioned above has been conducted, differ

47

from other cultures on a number of traits (Henrich, Heine, & Norenzayan, 2010). In

48

particular, participants from WEIRD cultures are sometimes at the far end of the

49

distribution—for instance in terms of individualism (Henrich et al., 2010). Schooling, which

50

is comprehensive in WEIRD cultures but absent from many other cultures, can exert a

51

profound influence on cognition, for instance through the acquisition of literacy (Dehaene,

52

2009) and numeracy (Dehaene, 1999; Gordon, 2004).

53

Regarding reasoning and argumentation, WEIRD cultures have a series of traits that,

54

while not necessarily specific to these cultures, might conspire to create the features

55

mentioned above. Compared to many other cultures, members of Western cultures: 1) have

56

long put a higher value on argumentation in their institutions, from science to law or politics

57

(Lloyd, 1996; Peng & Nisbett, 1999; especially compared to Eastern cultures, see Becker,

58

1986; Nakamura, 1964); 2) put relatively less stress on face-saving and social harmony (Kim

59

& Markus, 1999; Oetzel et al., 2001), which might allow for more confrontational and open

60

debates (Mercier, Deguchi, Van der Henst, & Yama, 2015); 3) adopt a different parenting

61

style in which children tend to argue more with adults: they question more freely their

62

decisions, and receive more explanations—although this difference seems to be restricted to

63

the middle and upper classes (Chouinard, Harris, & Maratsos, 2007; indeed, they talk more

64

with adults generally, Hart & Risley, 1995; Heath, 1983). All of these factors might make

65

argumentation a cognitive skill particularly valued in participants from WEIRD cultures.

4

66

The myside bias might be a cognitive response to a specific cultural environment in

67

which argumentation is highly valued and it is particularly important to be able to defend

68

one’s point of view. Two other traits might help explain the existence of a myside bias in

69

WEIRD cultures. First, in WEIRD cultures, individuals are confronted with a variety of

70

choices, values, and worldviews. In such cultures, it makes sense to anticipate having to

71

defend one’s choices, since it is likely that one will encounter people who have made different

72

choices (Schwartz, 2004). Second, many of these choices mostly have a symbolic value, so

73

that it arguably matters more to make a decision that is socially acceptable than an

74

intrinsically good decision. For instance, reasoning has been shown to lead customers towards

75

products they enjoy less, but which allow them to be perceived more positively by others

76

(Thompson & Norton, 2008; for review, see Mercier & Sperber, 2011). Even socially

77

consequential choices, such as voting, might mostly have a symbolic value (Sears, Lau, Tyler,

78

& Allen, 1980). The symbolic value of voting, and of political opinions more generally, might

79

help explain why voters in WEIRD cultures have a consistent myside bias when reasoning

80

about politics: it matters more that they have arguments to justify their opinions than that they

81

make otherwise sound opinions (Kahan et al., 2012; Taber & Lodge, 2006).

82

WEIRD cultures thus seem to have a number of traits that favor the development of

83

argumentative skills, traits which in turn might favor the emergence of a myside bias. In order

84

to test whether these cultural traits partly or entirely account for the relevant features of

85

reasoning—the efficiency of argumentation and the deficiencies of solitary reasoning—it is

86

necessary to study reasoning and argumentation in a population that does not share these

87

cultural traits. We first argue that a broad type of cultures—which we will call, in an ad-hoc

88

fashion, traditional cultures—differs in many relevant ways from WEIRD cultures. Then we

89

will argue that the population to which the participants recruited here belong, the K’iche’

90

Maya in Guatemala, share these traits.

5

91

Here we define traditional cultures as the human groups which are the broad opposite

92

of WEIRD cultures: small-scale groups which are not Western, educated, industrialized, or

93

rich (note that many human groups would thus fall between WEIRD and traditional cultures

94

as so defined). The fact that these cultures are not Western means that they do not share the

95

hypothetical Western values which cast argumentation in a positive light (although they might

96

hold other values to the same effect, see, e.g. Gluckman, 1967). Regarding lack of education

97

(in the sense of formal schooling), one of its most relevant consequences is a reluctance to

98

engage in hypothetical thinking. Experiments conducted in several unschooled populations

99

have revealed that most of their members fail to complete even very simple hypothetical

100

reasoning tasks (Cole, Gay, Glick, & Sharp, 1971; Luria, 1976; Scribner, 1977). This

101

reluctance to engage in hypothetical thinking could hinder argumentation, since

102

argumentation often relies on hypotheticals. Besides the lack of schooling, education also

103

differs in traditional societies in other ways. Of particular relevance here is that parenting in

104

traditional populations conforms to the pattern observed outside of middle and upper middle

105

class WEIRD populations: relatively little talk addressed to children, and in particular a very

106

small number of exchanges requiring reasons and explanations (Gauvain, Munroe, & Beebe,

107

2013). Because members of traditional cultures, compared to members of WEIRD cultures,

108

might value argumentation less, be more reluctant to engage in hypothetical thinking, and are

109

not trained to argue early on, they might be less likely to develop the argumentative skills

110

evidenced in the members of WEIRD cultures.

111

We argued above that the members of WEIRD cultures—particularly in the middle

112

and upper middle classes—are faced with a great variety of choices, and that many of these

113

choices are in large part symbolic. The choices facing members of traditional cultures differ

114

in both respects. As a rule, members of these cultures have far fewer choices: far fewer (if

115

any) products to buy, far fewer (if any) choice of occupation, far fewer (if any) choice of

6

116

places to live, far fewer (if any) choice of religion, far fewer (if any) choices of people to

117

befriend, etc. (see, Lévi-Strauss, 1966). This relative lack of choice suggests a lighter burden

118

of justification. Members of traditional cultures might thus have less use of a myside bias

119

which would help them defend their choices. Moreover, it has been argued that members of

120

traditional cultures make more life and death decisions than members of WEIRD cultures

121

(Diamond, 2012). Contrary to the members of WEIRD cultures, members of traditional

122

cultures do not live only in a human created environment in which many natural dangers are

123

eliminated (e.g. predation) or drastically reduced (e.g. many pathogens). This is reflected in

124

the lower life expectancy in traditional cultures compared to WEIRD cultures (e.g. Gurven &

125

Kaplan, 2007). It is thus plausible that for most decisions, intrinsic value matters more than

126

symbolic value for the members of traditional cultures relative to members of WEIRD

127

cultures. As a result, the myside bias could be disadvantageous for the former, as it leads to

128

intrinsically worse decisions, and advantageous for the latter, as it leads to easier to defend

129

symbolic decisions.

130

On the whole, it is thus plausible that members of traditional cultures, relative to

131

members of WEIRD cultures, reason in a way that is more practical (see Luria, 1976; Medin

132

& Atran, 2004) and more in line with the predictions of the individualistic view of reasoning.

133

Relative to members of WEIRD cultures, members of traditional cultures might suffer less

134

from the myside bias, and thus be more efficient solitary reasoners, while benefitting less

135

from argumentation.

136

In light of the evidence available, the relevant traits of traditional cultures mentioned

137

above appear to be present in the K’iche’ Maya who participated in the present experiments.

138

The K’iche’ are a preliterate Maya Amerindian group living in rural areas of Guatemala. Men

139

are mainly subsistence farmers and women do household maintenance work. They are

140

obviously not Western, and there is no evidence that their culture puts a particular value on

7

141

argumentation. The participants in our experiments had received no schooling as children and

142

were in the process of receiving a very moderate amount of schooling as adults. The pattern

143

of interactions with the children seems to follow the pattern typically found outside of middle

144

and upper classes in WEIRD cultures. A study of the interactions between K’iche’ adults and

145

children revealed that most of the utterances adults address to children are imperative and

146

very few are questions (Pye, 1986). There is thus little opportunity for argumentative

147

exchanges between children and adults. Overall, the K’iche’ do not seem to enjoy any of the

148

cultural traits that might make WEIRD cultures particularly congenial to argumentation.

149

Like other small-scale societies relying on substance farming, the K’iche’ face fewer

150

choices than members of WEIRD cultures. Few products are available for purchase, and they

151

have very little money to purchase them with (UNDP, 2010a, 2010b). The choice of

152

occupation and place to live is extremely restricted (UNDP, 2010a, 2010b, 2012, 2014).

153

Moreover, the environment is harsher than that faced by most members of WEIRD cultures

154

(for instance 94% of the population in the relevant district—Sololá—lacks food security, see

155

INE, 2011, p. 29; UNDP, 2010a; UNFPA, 2014). The risk of disease and early death is much

156

higher (INE, 2011; UNDP, 2010a; UNFPA, 2014). A myside bias might thus be less adaptive

157

in such an environment than in that of WEIRD cultures.

158

The improvement in performance yielded by argumentation, the myside bias which

159

explains poor solitary performance, and the argumentative skills which explain good

160

performance in group discussion are the main pieces of evidence in favor of the

161

argumentative theory of reasoning. This theory posits that reasoning is an evolved adaptation,

162

and that these features, which make it adaptive, should be relatively universal (Mercier &

163

Sperber, 2011). However, these features have mostly been documented among WEIRD

164

cultures. We have argued above that several traits of Western cultures might conspire to

165

explain these features, and that reasoning might exhibit different features in traditional

8

166

populations such as the K’iche’ Maya recruited in the present study. Experiments carried out

167

in such populations can thus provide crucial evidence to understand the function of human

168

reasoning. Accordingly, the goal of the present experiments is twofold. First, to test whether,

169

in this traditional population, discussion improves performance compared to solitary

170

reasoning. Second, if such an improvement was observed, to determine whether it could be

171

explained by the two features of reasoning that explain the gap in reasoning performance in

172

WEIRD populations: myside bias and sound ability to evaluate others’ arguments.

173 174

Methods

175

Participants. One hundred and forty preliterate participants were involved in this research, 57

176

in study 1 (48 females, Mage = 35.12 years, SD = 12.16, range 18-62 years) and 83 in study 2

177

(78 females, Mage = 43.89 years, SD = 12.49, range 21-76 years). The participants were

178

K’iche’ from ten different villages around the city of Nahualá in the department of Sololá,

179

Guatemala. The participants were recruited through an alphabetization program set up by the

180

CONALFA (National Committee for Alphabetization) in which they take part. The program

181

consisted of arithmetic and literacy classes dispensed in K’iche’. The participants were

182

supposed to spend three hours per week to learn to read and write, first in their native

183

language and later in Spanish, but few of them were able to attend the classes regularly.

184

Nearly all participants (N = 127, 91%) were in their first year of alphabetization, the rest in

185

their second year. Verbal informed consent was obtained from the participants. Each

186

participant received a reward—seeds or sewing threads—that they had requested during the

187

recruitment phase.

188 189

Design. Two studies were conducted and both had the same design (see Supplemental

190

Material for details). The tasks used in this research—conservation tasks—are designed to

9

191

assess the understanding of the invariance of physical quantities across physical

192

transformations (Dasen, 1972; Piaget & Inhelder, 1974), and discussion has been shown to

193

improve performance in WEIRD cultures (Doise & Mugny, 1984; Perret-Clermont, 1980).

194

We used weight/volume conservation tasks, in which participants must indicate how the water

195

level in two glasses changes when one object is introduced in each glass (Figure 1A). The

196

objects differ in some irrelevant dimension(s), such as weight or shape, but not volume; hence

197

the correct answer is that the water rises as much in the two glasses. All the participants first

198

completed two familiarization trials (whose presentation order was counterbalanced): In both

199

tasks, the experimenter provided participants with feedback (see Figure S1; no feedback was

200

provided at any other point of the experiment). The participants then completed a series of

201

three (Study 1) or two (Study 2) volume conservation tasks on their own (pre-test). Groups of

202

three (Study 1, N = 19, Study 2, N = 25) or four (Study 2, N = 2) individuals were then

203

formed randomly. The groups were given the instruction to arrive at a consensual answer for

204

each task (test). Finally, each participant had to solve the task on her own again (post-test)

205

(see Supplemental Material, Figure S1). In Study 1, a fourth, new task was presented to the

206

participants in the post-test, in order to test for transfer effects (Task 4).

207

The tasks used in Study 1 (Tasks 1, 2, and 3 at all phases, Task 4 as a transfer task) were

208

chosen based on results obtained by one of the authors (F.J.) with another traditional

209

population (in Papua New Guinea), in which participants only had to complete the tasks on

210

their own. We chose tasks for which there were no ceiling or floor effects in this other

211

traditional population. The tasks used in Study 2 were based on the results of Study 1. We

212

chose Task 2 because it elicited a lower rate of performance than Tasks 1 and 3 at the pre-test

213

of Study 1. Task 4 provided a baseline to evaluate the performance in Study 1, in which it was

214

used as a transfer task.

215

In each phase, the tasks were always presented in the same order. The positions of the

10

216

objects (left and right) were the same during the pre and post-test, and were inverted in the

217

test. During the pre- and the post-test, 114 participants were asked to justify their answers,

218

while 26 were asked instead to think aloud. For all participants, the justifications and think

219

aloud protocols in the pre- and post-test, as well as the discussion during test were recorded,

220

transcribed, translated from K’iche’ to Spanish, and coded by two individuals, one of whom

221

was blind to the hypotheses (inter-coder reliability: Kappa = .79, p < .001).

222 223

Procedure. Two native female experimenters were trained by one of the authors (T.C.), and

224

they conducted all the experiments. All the experiments were conducted in 2014. The

225

experimenters interacted with the participants in their native language. The translations from

226

Spanish to K’iche’ were done by one of the experimenters, the back-translation by the other

227

experimenter, with discrepancies resolved through discussion with one of the authors (T.C.).

228

The experiments took place in the village of each community, in the rooms where the

229

participants follow their alphabetization lessons. In order to ensure that the participants were

230

not discussing the tasks outside of the experimental context, when they were not being tested

231

they had to reintegrate their classroom and to continue to follow the lesson of the day. They

232

were also instructed not to interact until the end of the experiment.

233

In the familiarization phase, the participants were presented with the material: two

234

glasses and two pieces of clay (Play-Doh) (see Supplemental Material, Figure S1). We used

235

the same materials in the following tasks, except for Tasks 2 and 4 in which we used one

236

piece of clay and one piece of metal. The experimenter started the familiarization phase by

237

pouring the two glasses with water and invited the participants to observe that their level was

238

equal. Then she presented the first pair of objects in front of the two glasses. In Tasks 1 and 3,

239

the transformations—cut the ball in two, turn it into a cylinder—were made in front of the

240

participants, and the differences or similarities in weight or size were notified to them before

11

241

each trial. The experimenter then asked the participants: “If I put the balls in the two glasses,

242

their level of water will rise, do you think that it will rise more in this glass [The experimenter

243

pointed to one of the glasses]? Do you think it will rise more in this glass [The experimenter

244

pointed to the other glass]? Or it will rise the same in the two glasses?” All the tasks followed

245

the same instructions. During the test, participants were invited to discuss the tasks in groups

246

and to arrive at a consensual answer: “You can discuss now and agree on an answer.” After

247

the discussion, the experimenter asked: “Do you all agree? What is your answer?”

248

----------------------------------Figure 1 about here -----------------------------------

249 250 251 252

Results

253

At each stage of the studies, we computed the individual scores, assigning 1 to correct

254 255

answers and 0 to incorrect answers, and the group scores (addition of individual scores), using

256

real groups for the tests, and the equivalent nominal groups for the pre- and post-tests (Figure

257

1B, see Supplemental Material, Results for details). Comparing the individual scores, in both

258

studies we observed a significant improvement in performance between the pre-test and the

259

post-test (Study 1: MdnPre-test = 2, MdnPost-test = 3, Z = 4.79, p < .001, r = .44; Study 2: MdnPre-

260

test =

261

also significant when we counted as correct only correct answers accompanied by a correct

262

explanation, e.g. “because the objects have the same size” (Study 1: MdnPre-test = 2, MdnPost-test

263

= 3, Z = 5.04, p < .001, r = .45; Study 2: MdnPre-test = 0, MdnPost-test = 2, Z = 4.94, p < .001, r =

264

.36). Regarding group scores, in both studies we observed a significant improvement in

265

performance between the pre-test and the test (Study 1: MdnPre-test = 6, MdnTest = 9, Z = 3.64, p

266

< .001, r = .67; Study 2: MdnPre-test = 2, MdnTest = 6, Z = 3.80, p < .001, r = .53) but not

0, MdnPost-test = 2, Z = 5.33, p < .001, r = .43). The pre-test / post-test improvement was

12

267

between the test and the post-test (Study 1: MdnTest = 9 MdnPost-test = 8, Z = 1.47, p = .14;

268

Study 2: MdnTest = 6, MdnPost-test = 5, Z = .064 p = .95). Thus, group discussion significantly

269

improved the reasoning performance of preliterate individuals.

270

To test whether the myside bias could explain wrong answers at the pre-test, we

271

analyzed the reasons participants provided. The myside bias should limit the number of

272

reasons that go against the participants’ answers. Out of 141 explanations given by

273

participants providing the wrong answer, 1 contained no reason, 134 contained only reasons

274

supporting the participants’ answer, and 6 contained reasons against it. This result could also

275

reflect a task demand: participants were asked to explain their answers. Therefore, they might

276

have failed to mention reasons that they had considered but dismissed. To test this possibility,

277

a subset of participants had been asked not to explain their answers, but to think aloud while

278

they were trying to solve the tasks. Out of the 32 explanations given by participants providing

279

wrong answers in think aloud protocols, 3 mentioned reasons going against their final answer,

280

2 contained no reasons, while 27 contained only reasons supporting the participants’ final

281

answer (see Supplemental Material, Results for the detail of the coding).

282

To evaluate the soundness of argument evaluation, we contrasted the effects good and

283

bad arguments had on the outcome of the discussion. An argument could convince other

284

group members not because they think it is good, but because it is defended by the majority.

285

To examine such majority effects, we first analyzed the 43 discussions in which a participant

286

who had given the correct answer and the correct justification in the pre-test faced group

287

members who all agreed on the same wrong answer. In 33 (77%) of these discussions, the

288

group agreed on the correct answer. Moreover, in 8 out of the 10 remaining discussions, no

289

argument for the correct answer was offered. We also analyzed the 23 discussions in which a

290

participant who had given a wrong answer in the pre-test faced group members who all

291

agreed on the correct answer. In these discussions, the participant with a wrong answer never

13

292

convinced the group. Thus, a participant who defended an answer on her own was

293

significantly more likely to convince the group if she defended the correct answer than a

294

wrong answer (p < .001). As an illustration, Figure 2 represents the effects of correct and

295

incorrect arguments on the outcome of group discussion for the Task 4 of Study 2.

296

----------------------------------Figure 2 about here -----------------------------------

297 298 299 300 301

If the participants who adopted the correct answer did so because they had understood

302

the good argument, they might be able to use this new understanding to solve a transfer task.

303

In Study 1, we used a novel conservation task (Task 4) after the post-test. In Study 2, Task 4

304

was used in the pre-test. In Study 1, participants solved this task correctly more often (63%)

305

than in Study 2 (39%; p = .006).

306 307

14

Conclusion

308 309

The results of these studies show that preliterate individuals share some of the most

310

important features of reasoning previously documented in WEIRD populations: reasoning

311

performance significantly improves with discussion; argument production is marked by the

312

myside bias; argument evaluation is efficient, enabling participants to discriminate between

313

good and bad arguments and to be convinced by good arguments.

314

These results do not demonstrate that these features are universal. We might have

315

considered the wrong traits of WEIRD cultures as being potentially relevant to the shaping of

316

reasoning and argumentation. Other cultural traits, which are shared by WEIRD cultures and

317

the Mayan indigenous group studied here but absent in other cultures, might in fact be

318

determinant. Still, the K’iche’ differ from WEIRD cultures in many of the traits that could

319

have plausibly explained why the relevant features of reasoning are observed in WEIRD

320

cultures: the value placed on argumentation, the fact that children and adults exchange many

321

arguments, the fact that people feel they have to justify many of their choices, and the

322

relatively low costs of poor decisions. We thus suggest that the present investigation helps

323

make the case that these features are not culturally acquired.

324

The potential universality of these features of reasoning is relevant to the debates

325

about the function of reasoning. Individualist theories of reasoning do not necessarily predict

326

poor argumentative performance, but it is not clear how they can explain the improvement in

327

performance following group discussion. As for the myside bias, it runs directly against their

328

predictions. By contrast, these features of reasoning support the argumentative theory of

329

reasoning.

330 331

The argumentative theory of reasoning suggests that these features are adaptive features of reasoning. They would be adaptive because they enable reasoning to fulfill its

15

332

main function, argumentation, which in turns greatly facilitates communication (the

333

evolutionary rationale is exposed in Mercier & Sperber, 2011). As expected if these features

334

are adaptive, not only are they extremely robust in adults from WEIRD populations (Mercier,

335

in pressb; Mercier & Sperber, 2011), but they have now been observed in a culture that differs

336

in many relevant ways from WEIRD cultures, and there is no strong evidence that they are

337

absent from other cultures (Mercier, 2011a; Mercier et al., 2015). Moreover these features

338

seem to develop early (Castelain, Bernard, Van der Henst, & Mercier, in press; Mercier,

339

2011b).

340

Although research into cultural variation can yield precious insights about cognition, it

341

is possible that cross-cultural psychology is overly geared towards differences rather than

342

similarities. Focusing on potential universals is also of tremendous theoretical importance, in

343

particular for testing adaptive hypotheses. We hope the present research can be another step in

344

this direction (for another recent example using the same population, see Fontanari, Gonzalez,

345

Vallortigara, & Girotto, 2014).

346 347

Data availability: All the data are available at this url:

348

https://sites.google.com/site/hugomercier/Data%20Evidence%20for%20core%20features%20

349

of%20reasoning.zip?attredirects=0

Acknowledgments: This research was carried out thanks to an Ambizione grant (PZ00P1_142388 / 1) from the Swiss National Science Foundation to H.M. We thank all the participants of the study, the CONALFA association and their teachers from the Sololá department, Francisca Ixquiactap Lopez for the logistic, and María Guarchaj and Catalina Sac Tambriz, the two experimenters who conducted the studies.

16

350 351

17

352

References

353

Baumeister, R. F., & Masicampo, E. J. (2010). Conscious thought is for facilitating social and

354

cultural interactions: How mental simulations serve the animal–culture interface.

355

Psychological Review, 117(3), 945.

356 357 358 359 360

Becker, C. B. (1986). Reasons for the lack of argumentation and debate in the Far East. International Journal of Intercultural Relations, 10(1), 75–92. Billig, M. (1996). Arguing and Thinking: A Rhetorical Approach to Social Psychology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Castelain, T., Bernard, S., Van der Henst, J. B., & Mercier, H. (in press). The influence of

361

power and reason on young Maya children’s endorsement of testimony.

362

Developmental Science.

363

Chouinard, M. M., Harris, P. L., & Maratsos, M. P. (2007). Children’s questions: A

364

mechanism for cognitive development. Monographs of the Society for Research in

365

Child Development, i–129.

366 367 368 369 370 371

Cole, M., Gay, J., Glick, J. A., & Sharp, D. W. (1971). The cultural context of learning and thinking. New York: Basic Books. Dasen, P. R. (1972). Cross-cultural Piagetian research: A summary. Journal of Cross-Cultural Psychology, 3(1), 23–40. Dehaene, S. (1999). The Number Sense: How the Mind Creates Mathematics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

372

Dehaene, S. (2009). Reading in the brain: The new science of how we read. London: Penguin.

373

Descartes, R. (1637). Discours de la méthode. Paris: Vrin.

374

Doise, W., & Mugny, G. (1984). The Social Development of the Intellect. Oxford: Pergamon

375

Press.

18

376

Fontanari, L., Gonzalez, M., Vallortigara, G., & Girotto, V. (2014). Probabilistic cognition in

377

two indigenous Mayan groups. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences,

378

201410583. http://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.1410583111

379

Gauvain, M., Munroe, R. L., & Beebe, H. (2013). Children’s questions in cross-cultural

380

perspective a four-culture study. Journal of Cross-Cultural Psychology, 44(7), 1148–

381

1165.

382

Gibbard, A. (1990). Wise Choices, Apt Feelings. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

383

Gluckman, M. (1967). The judicial process among the Barotse of Northern Rhodesia

384 385 386 387 388 389 390 391

(Zambia). Manchester: Manchester University Press. Gordon, P. (2004). Numerical cognition without words: Evidence from Amazonia. Science, 306(5695), 496–499. Gurven, M., & Kaplan, H. (2007). Longevity among hunter-gatherers: a cross-cultural examination. Population and Development Review, 33(2), 321–365. Hahn, U., & Oaksford, M. (2007). The rationality of informal argumentation: A bayesian approach to reasoning fallacies. Psychological Review, 114(3), 704–732. Hart, B., & Risley, T. R. (1995). Meaningful differences in the everyday experience of young

392

American children. Baltimore: P H Brookes. Retrieved from

393

http://psycnet.apa.org/psycinfo/1995-98021-000

394 395 396 397 398 399

Heath, S. B. (1983). Ways with words: Language, life and work in communities and classrooms. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Henrich, J., Heine, S. J., & Norenzayan, A. (2010). The weirdest people in the world. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 33(2-3), 61–83. INE. (2011). Caracterización República de Guatemala 2008/2011. Guatemala: Instituto Nacional de Estadistica Guatemala. Retrieved from

19

400

http://www.ine.gob.gt/sistema/uploads/2014/02/26/L5pNHMXzxy5FFWmk9NHCrK9

401

x7E5Qqvvy.pdf

402

Janis, I. L. (1982). Groupthink (2nd Rev). Boston: Houghton Mifflin.

403

Kahan, D. M., Peters, E., Wittlin, M., Slovic, P., Ouellette, L. L., Braman, D., & Mandel, G.

404

(2012). The polarizing impact of science literacy and numeracy on perceived climate

405

change risks. Nature Climate Change, 2(10), 732–735.

406 407 408 409 410 411

Kahneman, D. (2003). A perspective on judgment and choice: Mapping bounded rationality. American Psychologist, 58(9), 697–720. Kim, H., & Markus, H. R. (1999). Deviance or uniqueness, harmony or conformity? A cultural analysis. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 77(4), 785. Koriat, A., Lichtenstein, S., & Fischhoff, B. (1980). Reasons for confidence. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Learning and Memory and Cognition, 6, 107–118.

412

Laughlin, P. R. (2011). Group Problem Solving. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

413

Lévi-Strauss, C. (1966). The scope of anthropology. Current Anthropology, 7(2), 112–123.

414

Lloyd, G. E. R. (1996). Adversaries and Authorities. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

415

Luria, A. R. (1976). Cognitive Development its Cultural and Social Foundations. Cambridge,

416 417 418 419

MA: Harvard University Press. Medin, D. L., & Atran, S. (2004). The native mind: Biological categorization and reasoning in development and across cultures. Psychological Review, 111(4), 960–982. Mellers, B., Ungar, L., Baron, J., Ramos, J., Gurcay, B., Fincher, K., … others. (2014).

420

Psychological strategies for winning a geopolitical forecasting tournament.

421

Psychological Science, 25(5), 1106–1115.

422 423

Mercier, H. (in pressa). Confirmation (or myside) bias. In R. Pohl (Ed.), Cognitive Illusions (2nd ed.). London: Psychology Press.

20

424

Mercier, H. (in pressb). Reasoning and argumentation. In V. A. Thompson & L. J. Ball (Eds.),

425

International Handbook of Thinking & Reasoning. Hove: Psychology Press.

426

Mercier, H. (2011a). On the universality of argumentative reasoning. Journal of Cognition

427 428 429 430 431 432

and Culture, 11, 85–113. Mercier, H. (2011b). Reasoning serves argumentation in children. Cognitive Development, 26(3), 177–191. Mercier, H. (2011c). When experts argue: explaining the best and the worst of reasoning. Argumentation, 25(3), 313–327. Mercier, H., Deguchi, M., Van der Henst, J.-B., & Yama, H. (2015). The benefits of

433

argumentation are cross-culturally robust: The case of Japan. Thinking & Reasoning,

434

(ahead-of-print), 1–15.

435 436 437 438 439 440 441 442 443

Mercier, H., & Sperber, D. (2011). Why do humans reason? Arguments for an argumentative theory. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 34(2), 57–74. Moshman, D., & Geil, M. (1998). Collaborative reasoning: Evidence for collective rationality. Thinking and Reasoning, 4(3), 231–248. Nakamura, H. (1964). Ways of Thinking of Eastern Peoples: India, China, Tibet, Japan. Hawaii: University of Hawaii Press. Nickerson, R. S. (1998). Confirmation bias: A ubiquitous phenomena in many guises. Review of General Psychology, 2, 175–220. Oetzel, J., Ting-Toomey, S., Masumoto, T., Yokochi, Y., Pan, X., Takai, J., & Wilcox, R.

444

(2001). Face and facework in conflict: A cross-cultural comparison of China,

445

Germany, Japan, and the United States. Communication Monographs, 68(3), 235–258.

446 447

Peng, K., & Nisbett, R. E. (1999). Culture, dialectics and reasoning about contradiction. American Psychologist, 54(9), 741–754.

21

448 449 450

Perret-Clermont, A.-N. (1980). Social Interaction and Cognitive Development in Children. London: Academic Press. Petty, R. E., & Wegener, D. T. (1998). Attitude change: Multiple roles for persuasion

451

variables. In D. T. Gilbert, S. Fiske, & G. Lindzey (Eds.), The Handbook of Social

452

Psychology (pp. 323–390). Boston: McGraw-Hill.

453

Piaget, J. (1928). Judgment and Reasoning in the Child. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

454

Piaget, J., & Inhelder, B. (1974). The Child’s Construction of Quantities. London: Routledge.

455

Pye, C. (1986). Quiché Mayan speech to children. Journal of Child Language, 13(1), 85–100.

456

Rowe, G., & Wright, G. (1999). The Delphi technique as a forecasting tool: issues and

457

analysis. International Journal of Forecasting, 15(4), 353–375.

458

Schwartz, B. (2004). The Paradox of Choice: Why More is Less. New York: Harper Collins.

459

Scribner, S. (1977). Modes of thinking and ways of speaking: Culture and logic reconsidered.

460

In P. N. Johnson-Laird & P. C. Wason (Eds.), Thinking: Readings in cognitive science

461

(pp. 483–500). New York: Cambridge University Press.

462

Sears, D. O., Lau, R. R., Tyler, T. R., & Allen, H. M. (1980). Self-interest vs. symbolic

463

politics in policy attitudes and presidential voting. American Political Science Review,

464

74(03), 670–684.

465 466

Slavin, R. E. (1995). Cooperative Learning: Theory, Research, and Practice (Vol. 2nd). London: Allyn and Bacon.

467

Smith, M. K., Wood, W. B., Adams, W. K., Wieman, C., Knight, J. K., Guild, N., & Su, T. T.

468

(2009). Why peer discussion improves student performance on in-class concept

469

questions. Science, 323(5910), 122.

470

Stanovich, K. E. (2004). The Robot’s Rebellion. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

471

Taber, C. S., & Lodge, M. (2006). Motivated skepticism in the evaluation of political beliefs.

472

American Journal of Political Science, 50(3), 755–769.

22

473 474

Tesser, A., & Conlee, M. C. (1975). Some effects of time and thought on attitude polarization. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 31(2), 262–270.

475

Thompson, D. V., & Norton, M. I. (2008). The social utility of feature creep. In A. Lee & D.

476

Soman (Eds.), Advances in Consumer Research (pp. 181–184). Duluth, MN:

477

Association for Consumer Research.

478

Trouche, E., Sander, E., & Mercier, H. (2014). Arguments, more than confidence, explain the

479

good performance of reasoning groups. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General,

480

143(5), 1958–1971.

481

UNDP. (2010a). Informe Nacional de Desarrollo Humano 2009/2010: Cifras para el

482

desarrollo humano Sololá. Guatemala: UNDP. Retrieved from

483

http://desarrollohumano.org.gt/sites/default/files/07%20Fasciculo%20Solola.pdf

484

UNDP. (2010b). Informe Nacional de Desarrollo Humano 2009/2010: Hacia un Estado para

485

el desarrollo humano. Guatemala: UNDP. Retrieved from

486

http://hdr.undp.org/sites/default/files/guatemala_indh_2009-10.pdf

487

UNDP. (2012). Informe nacional de desarrollo humano 2011/2012: Guatemala, ¿un país de

488

oportunidades para la juventud? Guatemala: UNDP. Retrieved from

489

http://desarrollohumano.org.gt/sites/default/files/INDH%202011_2012.pdf

490 491 492

UNDP. (2014). Human Development Report. Sustaining Human Progress: Reducing Vulnerabilities and Building Resilience. (UNDP). New York. UNFPA. (2014). Análisis de la Situación de País 2010/2014. Guatemala: UNFPA. Retrieved

493

from

494

https://www.unfpa.org/sites/default/files/portaldocument/Guatemala_UNDAF%20201

495

0-2014.pdf.pdf

23

Figure(s)

Fig. 1. (A) Illustration of the four tasks. (B) Box plots representing the normalized scores for the groups in Study 1 (Tasks 1, 2, 3) and Study 2 (Tasks 2, 4). The groups are the real discussion groups in the test and the nominal groups comprising the same participants in the pre- and post-tests. The boxes represent the middle half of each sample. !

Figure(s)

Fig. 2. Details of the performance for Task 4 in Study 2. For the pre-test and the post-test, each disk represents a nominal group, and the proportion of red (resp. green) in the disks represents the proportion of incorrect (resp. correct) answers. For the test, each disk represents a group and the color represents the outcome of the discussion. A red (resp. green) surrounding circle indicates that an argument for the wrong answer (resp. the correct argument for the correct answer) was uttered at least once during the discussion. !

Supplementary Material (Hyperlink only displayed in PDF) Click here to download Supplementary Material (Hyperlink only displayed in PDF): SM Evidence for benefits of argumentation in

Evidence for benefits of argumentation in a Mayan ...

International Journal of Intercultural Relations, 10(1), 75–92. 357. Billig, M. (1996). Arguing and Thinking: A Rhetorical Approach to Social Psychology. 358. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 359. Castelain, T., Bernard, S., Van der Henst, J. B., & Mercier, H. (in press). The influence of. 360 power and reason on young ...

1MB Sizes 2 Downloads 230 Views

Recommend Documents

Argumentation in Science
Collaboration. Groups should place the cards in order based on. The magnitude of impact on the world in the year they were invented. Use Consensus to ...

LacadenaWichman-2000-Distribution of Lowland Mayan ...
Whoops! There was a problem loading this page. Retrying... LacadenaWichman-2000-Distribution of Lowland Mayan Languages.pdf. LacadenaWichman-2000-Distribution of Lowland Mayan Languages.pdf. Open. Extract. Open with. Sign In. Main menu. Displaying La

Preliminary evidence for a processing error in the biosynthesis of ...
Our data provide evidence for the existence of AP in cultured skin fibroblasts and ..... with a greater than 75% recovery ofAPA. AP bound less ... E. Ranieri, B. Paton and A. Poulos. 15.0-. E 10.0. 0. E°. CD. 0. CL. E. -S. 0._. Ca c 5.0-. 0. c, cn.

An Argumentation-based Framework for Deliberation in ...
eration policy, and the counterargument generation policy are case-based tech- niques. For join deliberation .... like generation and selection of arguments and counterarguments. In our approach, the ...... and languages that support argumentation, b

Reasoning serves argumentation in children
that children possess basic argument skills, (ii) that they are able reap the benefits of ... adults when they use reasoning in the wrong contexts. ..... for argumentation but that it still needs to develop to reach a stage of adult competency. ....

Graduate Education in Argumentation and Forensics: A ...
Graduate Education in Argumentation and Forensics: A Note on the 1996 SCA Graduate Directory. Michael W. Shelton. Mr. Shelton is a doctoral candidate and teaching assistant in the .... however, a good guide to the availability of graduate programs wi

A scalar account of Mayan positional roots Robert ...
A scalar account of Mayan positional roots. Robert Henderson. Most Mayan languages have a large class of roots traditionally called "positionals" in the descriptive literature. While positional roots are usually classified morphologically, I will sho

Argumentation-based Information Exchange in Prediction Markets
Essentially, a Multiagent Prediction Market (MPM) is composed of (a) a ... ing the likelihood of that specific prediction to be correct, i.e. a degree of confidence.

Roots and Words in Chol (Mayan): A Distributed ...
deserves thanks for teaching me how, on the other hand, to abstract far away from this context and ponder the philosophical problems of language. Entering the ...

The Ethics of Argumentation in Intercollegiate Debate
1Kurt Andersen, "The Best and the Glibbest," Time, 15 March 1982, p. 10. ... support or oppose a policy proposal because of its perceived .... the computer.

Benefits of Labor Mobility in a Currency Union
May 22, 2018 - BG31 - Severozapaden, MIG. BG32 - Severen tsentralen, MIG. BG33 - Severoiztochen, MIG. BG34 - Yugoiztochen, MIG. BG41 - Yugozapaden ...

Benefits of Participating in SIM.pdf
Access to a regional health connector (RHC), dedicated to connecting. practice sites to resources that can improve patient outcomes. • Connection to local public health resources and data related to population health. Business Support • Access to

Mayan Agriculture .pdf
Sign in. Page. 1. /. 2. Loading… Page 1 of 2. Page 1 of 2. Page 2 of 2. Page 2 of 2. Mayan Agriculture .pdf. Mayan Agriculture .pdf. Open. Extract. Open with.

Argumentation in Science - National Early College Conference
members. Do not reveal your cards until it is your turn. Person #1 places one card in the center of the table. Make a claim “This invention had the greatest impact on the word when it was incented….” State evidence to support the claim. Team me

Benefits of Participating in SIM.pdf
providers to influence comorbidities between physical and behavioral health issues. Page 1 of 1. Benefits of Participating in SIM.pdf. Benefits of Participating in ...

A Systematic Theory of Argumentation: The pragma-dialectical approach
solution. “Fundamental” philosophical reflection is essential because the crucial issues of the discipline are at stake. No consistent scientific practices are ...... Data. Claim. Warrant. Backing. 17 In practice, it is often difficult (if not im

A Systematic Theory of Argumentation: The pragma-dialectical approach
Introduction. 1. 2. The realm of argumentation studies. 9. Argumentation theory as normative pragmatics. 9. The philosophical estate. 11. The theoretical estate. 18 ...... In the model, several fixed elements play a role. Facts (data) are adduced in

Argumentation-based Example Interchage for ...
produced have to be postprocessed in order to remove the order relationship ..... Table 2 shows that among all the multiagent induction strategies, DAGGER is ...

The-Mayan-Prophecies-Unlocking-The-Secrets-Of-A-Lost ...
There was a problem previewing this document. Retrying... Download. Connect more apps... Try one of the apps below to open or edit this item. The-Mayan-Prophecies-Unlocking-The-Secrets-Of-A-Lost-Civilization.pdf. The-Mayan-Prophecies-Unlocking-The-Se

arguments of interpretation and argumentation ... - Fabrizio Macagno
cal control of the sock at some point before that discovery was made. In this case .... In this case the scientific law governing the velocity of bullets does not need ...

Articles - COGENCY | Journal of Reasoning and Argumentation
plex argumentation that are based on methods of legal interpretation and on the application of specific legal argument forms such as analogy argu- mentation, a contrario argumentation, teleological-evaluative argumenta- tion and argumentation from un

arguments of interpretation and argumentation ... - Fabrizio Macagno
the State, provides a sufficient basis to uphold the constitutionality of the marriage statutes. Any change to the bedrock principle that limits marriage to persons of the opposite sex, the State argues, must come from the democratic process. This ch

ease-merchandising-benefits-on-steroid-in-favor-of-wart-in ...
Whoops! There was a problem loading more pages. Retrying... ease-merchandising-benefits-on-steroid-in-favor-of-wart-in-foodstuffs-1499608386263.pdf.