Ethical Motives for Strategic Voting Christopher Li and Ricardo Pique Cebrecos∗ January 17, 2014

Abstract We propose an alternative approach to modeling strategic voting in large elections. In particular, we examine strategic voting in the presence of ethical voters, who follow a group-welfare maximizing voting rule. This rule may require them to vote strategically, that is, to vote for a candidate that is not their most preferred. The model delivers comparative statics that link the degree of strategic voting with various electoral parameters. We show that strategic voting is non-monotonic in the popularity of the Condorcet loser. This observation reconciles the apparently contradicting empirical evidence and is robust to more general specifications of the model.

JEL classification: D72 Keywords: Strategic Voting, Ethical Voters, Large Elections



Li: Northwestern University, [email protected]: Northwestern University, [email protected]. We are grateful to Georgy Egorov, Timothy Feddersen, Sandeep Baliga and Alvaro Sandroni for helpful advice and comments. We would also like to thank Samir Mamadehussene and Kym Pram for useful insights.

1

1

Introduction

In a three-candidate election where one of the candidates is a Condorcet loser, it is sometimes in the interest of the voters to vote for their second most preferred candidate to prevent the Condorcet loser winning.1 This phenomenon is typically referred to as strategic voting. The intuitive rationale for such a behavior is that a voter should not “waste” his vote on candidates who have little chance of winning. There is strong evidence of strategic voting in various elections. Many empirical studies on the topic have analyzed British elections. UK politics is conducive to strategic voting because the opposition to the main center-right party is divided between two center-left parties. The evidence from the UK elections shows that the extent of strategic voting ranges from 5% to 17%, as measured by the proportion of strategic votes (see Galbraith and Rae (1989), Heath and Evans (1994), Johnston and Pattie (1991), Lanoue and Bowler (1992), Niemi et al. (1992)). Strategic voting has also been documented in elections in Canada (Blais and Nadeau (1996), Germany (Spenkuch (2013)2 ) and the US (Abramson et al. (1992)). Answering the questions of when and to what extent strategic voting occurs is one of the central motivations behind the theory of voting. Seminal works by Palfrey (1989), Cox(1994,1997) and Myerson and Webber (1993) identify conditions that induce strategic voting. In those models, the incentive to vote strategically (or the lack thereof) is manifested in a rather stark way: in equilibrium, voters either completely abandon all but two candidates or split their votes evenly.3 More recent works by Picketty (2000) and 1

A voter supports candidate i if i is her most favored candidate. The author’s finding is particularly significant as he shows that 35% of voters abandon their most preferred candidate if they consider he has no possibility of winning the race. 3 The literature typically refers to the former as a Duvergerian Equilibrium and the latter as a Non-Duvergerian Equilibrium. Fey (1997) provides a rationale based on dynamic 2

2

Myatt (2007) provide a theoretical foundation for partial strategic voting by exploring the effect of incomplete information on the incentive for strategic voting.4 Existing works on strategic voting belong to the rational voting paradigm, where analysis is often complicated by issues such as multiplicity of equilibria. In this paper, we explore strategic voting in an ethical voter model in the spirit of Feddersen and Sandroni (2006a, 2006b). We assume that a fraction of voters are ethical in that, instead of taking an action that maximizes private utility, they follow a voting rule that maximizes the aggregate welfare of those with similar political ideology.5 The proposed model is tractable and delivers comparative statics of strategic voting with respect to various electoral parameters such as the importance of the election and the degree of partisanship. In particular, the model reconciles seemingly contradicts claims in the literature regarding the relationship between strategic voting and the popularity of the Condorcet loser. Cain (1978) provides an informal argument that strategic voting disappears when the popularity of the Condorcet loser is high. On the other hand, Myatt (2007) found that strategic voting is increasing in the popularity of the Condorcet loser, although he claims the result “runs against established intuition” (Myatt pg. 269). Empirical analyses on this issue have failed to yield an unified conclusion, adding to the mystery.6 In our model, strategic voting increases in the popularity of the Condorcet loser in some range and decreases for others. We provide a stylized account of UK elections in the stability for selecting the Duvergerian Equilibrium. 4 Empirical studies have shown that various degrees of strategic voting have occurred in UK and Canadian elections (see Cain (1978), Niemi, Whitten and Franklin (1992), Heath and Evans (1994), Blais and Nadeau (1996)). 5 The ethical voters in our model constitute an example of rule-utilitarians (see Harsanyi 1980 and 1977 for a discussion) 6 Fisher (2000) concludes a positive relationship while Blais and Nadeau (1996) show the opposite correlation for the 1988 Canadian Election.

3

1980s to support this result. In addition to providing a more comprehensive understanding of strategic voting, our model contributes to the emerging literature on ethical voters/agents. While the application of ethical agents to economic modeling is relatively new, the philosophical roots of the concept have been well established (see Harsanyi (1977) and (1980) for a background). Harsanyi was the first to discuss, via example, the implications of ethical agents in an electoral setting. Feddersen and Sandroni (2006a) build on Harsayni’s idea to model turnout in large elections, and their results are shown to fit the data better than rational voting models (see Coate and Conlin (2004)).7 Note that Feddersen and Sandroni (2006a) study two-candidate elections and therefore cannot account for strategic voting.8 Recently, Piolatto and Schuett (2012) use ethical voters to explain the demand for political news. The results in these studies, as well as the ones in this paper, are a testament that the ethical agent framework is particularly useful not only due to their tractability but, more importantly, because of their capacity to produce new insights. Thus, ethical voters should not be seen as a mere technical trick to simplify analysis of mass behavior. Evidence suggests that ethical motives, including a desire to follow rules that the agent considers as morally superior, play a significant role in mass behavior.9 It should not be surprising that the ethical agent models can provide a reasonable characterization of voting behavior and other phenomena such as political activism and charity, where motives that transcend self-interest are present. The rest of this paper is organized as follows. The model is described in the next section. In section 3, we characterize the ethical voting rule and present our comparative statics results. Section 4 provides several extensions 7

In Feddersen and Sandroni (2006a and 2006b), ethical voters have opposing objectives and act strategically. 8 Turnout can be studied jointly with strategic voting in our model, see section 4 9 For example, Blais (2000) shows that many voter vote out of a sense of civic duty.

4

to the general model, including one which allows us to analyse the turnout and strategic voting decisions jointly. Section 5 concludes.

2

The Model

We focus on a large election with three candidates, one of whom is a Condorcet loser. For convenience, we shall refer to the Condorcet loser as the extremist and the two other candidates as centrists: the center-left and the center-right. To approximate a large election, we assume a measure one of voters. Voting is costless and mandatory (this is relaxed in section 4) and the winner is decided by majority. It is commonly known that a measure ke of the voters will vote for the extremist. Thus ke represents the popularity of the extremist. The assumption that the extremist is the Condorcet loser implies that ke < 12 . The rest of the electorate are centrist supporters. We assume that centrist supporters obtain utility w > 0 in the the event that either centrists wins. Alternatively, one can think of −w as the disutility associated with the extremist candidate winning. Since w reflects the magnitude of dislike for the extremist, we interpret w as the importance of the election for the centrist supporters. In general, different centrist voters may attach different values to a center-left victory and a center-right victory, but this generalization will not alter the results in any qualitative way (see section 4). The centrist voters are heterogeneous in their preferences over the centrist. They are endowed with ideal points drawn independently from an uniform distribution on the interval [0, 1], where 0 and 1 are the position of the center-left and center-right respectively. Voter x (we refer to a voter by his ideal point) incurs a cost of θx for voting for the center-left and a cost

5

θ(1 − x) for voting for the center-right.10 We interpret θ as the degree of partisanship among centrist voters, since a higher θ implies a higher utility loss for x if he votes for his less preferred centrist. In sum, voter x’s (personal) utility of voting for the center-left and the center-right are respectively:

wp − θx wp − θ(1 − x) where p is the probability that a centrist candidate is elected. We assume that some voters vote base on his personal utility, and thus they will vote for the centrist closer to their ideal points. The rest of the centrist voters are ethical, whose characteristic is described below. We assume that the fraction of ethical voters, qc is an uniform random variable on [0, 1]. The ethical voters follow a voting rule that maximizes the expected welfare of the centrist supporters (See Harsayni(1977,1980) for justification). We refer to this rule as the ethical voting rule. A given ethical voting rule may require some ethical voters to vote against their personal utility.11 Without the loss of generality, the voting rule is of the cut-off type: a voting rule σc ∈ [0, 1] instructs the ethical voters with ideal points x > σc to vote for the center-right, and those with ideal points x ≤ σc to vote for center-left. Fix a particular rule σc , there is an expected social cost for the centrist voters

10

That is, we assume that the voters dislike expressing their support for a political platform that is not their ideal. Brennan (2001) states that in the context of a large election, “the most important question in determining who (a voter) votes for is what she is prepared to cheer for (and boo) in the electoral context.” (quote from Brennan pg. 226). Studies by Fischer (1996), Kan and Yang (2001) and Laband et al. (2009), among others, provide evidence that expressive considerations are significant factors in voting. 11 One can formalize the notion of ethical voters by assuming that they obtain utility φ > θ for following the ethical voting rule. See Feddersen and Sandroni (2006a) for an example.

6

(ethical and non-ethical), which is:   1 1 1 θ θ 2 = (σc2 − σc + ) + E qc θ(σc − σc + ) + (1 − qc )θ 2 4 2 2 8 Let p(σc ) denote the probability of centrist victory induced by the voting rule σc , the aggregate welfare of centrist supporters is:



1 1 F (σc ) = wp(σc ) − E − σc + )) + (1 − qc )θ 2 4 θ 1 θ = wp(σc ) − (σc2 − σc + ) − 2 2 8 qc (θ(σc2



Let σc∗ denote the maximizer of F (σc ). It exists because F (σc ) is a continuous function on a compact domain. It is easy to see that F (σc ) is symmetric around 21 because the ideal points are drawn from an uniform distribution. The symmetry of the objective function implies that the rule σc is equivalent to the rule 1 − σc . Thus, we restrict the domain of the maximization problem to [0, 12 ]. That is, we assume that ethical voters rally behind the center-right.12 Observe that the ethical voters engage in strategic voting if σc∗ ∈ [0, 12 ), since ethical voters with ideal points in [σc∗ , 21 ] are voting against his personal utility. We interpret 2( 12 − σc∗ ) as the degree of strategic voting. For a given σc , the probability of centrists winning is the probability that

12

Skewness in the distribution of ideal points is sufficient to break the indifference between the two rules and dispose of this assumption.

7

the center-right receives more votes than ke :     1 Pr (1 − ke ) (1 − qc ) + qc (1 − σc ) ≥ ke 2 ! ke 1 −2 e =Pr qc ≥ 1−k 1 − σc 2 Since qc is distributed uniformly, this means: ( p(σc ) = max 0, 1 −

ke − 12 1−ke 1 − σc 2

)

and the objective function F (σc ) can be written as: ( F (σc ) = w · max 0, 1 −

3

ke − 12 1−ke 1 − σc 2

)

θ 1 θ − (σc2 − σc + ) − 2 2 8

Results

For ke ≤ 13 , the centrists win with certainty.13 Thus, maximizing F is equivalent to minimizing the expected social cost, and therefore ethical voters will split their vote (i.e. σc∗ = 21 ). This is very intuitive: there is no incentive for strategic voting if it has no bearing on the outcomes. For the remainder of the paper, we focus on the non-trivial scenario 13 < ke < 12 . ke Denote k˜e = 1−k (i.e. the ratio of extremist supporters to centrist supe porters) for simplicity of the notation. Note that k˜e is a monotonic transformation of ke and thus they have the same interpretation (i.e. the popularity 13

We assume here the centrist candidate wins the election in the event of a tie.

8

of the extremist). Proposition 1. There exists a threshold value of k˜e (call it k¯e ) such that the ethical voters split their votes (i.e. σc∗ = 21 ) if k˜e ≥ k¯e , and vote strategically (i.e. σc∗ < 21 ) if k˜e < k¯e . Moreover, whenever strategic voting is optimal, σc∗ < 1 − k˜e . Corollary 1. k¯e is increasing in w and decreasing in θ. Proposition 1 agrees with claims by Cain (1978) and others that the incentive to vote strategically disappears when the Condorcet loser has high popularity (though not high enough for a majority). Recall our interpretation of w as the importance of election and θ as the degree of partisanship of centrist voters. Corollary 1 therefore offers two empirically testable implications: one is more likely to observe strategic voting in important elections (i.e. presidential and parliamentary elections) and when the centrist supporters are less partisan in their preferences of the two centrists. Proposition 2 below provides some characterization of the threshold value k¯e . Proposition 2. 1. For

θ w

≤ 83 , k¯e = 1 −

2. For

8 3

<

θ , w

1−

θ 16w

θ . 16w

< k¯e < min{ 12 +

θ 1 , 8w 2

+

 1 θ −2 } w

Corollary 2. Complete strategic voting (i.e. σc∗ = 0) occurs if and only if 1 θ θ + 8w ≤ k˜e ≤ 1 − 16w . 2 Figure 1 below summarizes our results so far. So far, we have explored conditions under which strategic voting is optimal. This is only one part of the comparative statics. We will now relate the degree of strategic voting and the electoral parameters conditional on strategic voting being optimal. 9

Figure 1: Behavior of Ethical Voters Proposition 3. Given strategic voting is optimal (i.e. σ ∗ < 12 ), the degree of strategic voting is increasing in the importance of election and the popularity ∗ ∗ c c ≤ 0), while it is decreasing in the cost of the extremist (i.e. ∂σ ≤ 0 and ∂σ ˜ ∂w ∂ ke ∂σc∗ of voting (i.e. ∂θ ≥ 0,). The inequalities are strict if σc∗ > 0. The comparative statics with respect to w and θ are expected given their interpretations. The more interesting observation is that for moderate popularity of the extremist (i.e. values of ke that induces strategic voting), small increases in the popularity induces a higher incentive to vote strategically. Combine this observation with Proposition 1, we see a non-monotonic (and discontinuous) relationship between strategic voting and the popularity of the extremist (see Figure 2). This new insight reconciles the contradictory empirical findings on this issue (see Cain (1978), Fisher (2000) and Blais and Nadeau (1996)): if the support for the extremist is low and variation is small in the data, then the econometrician is likely to observe a positive correlation between the popularity of the extremist and strategic voting; if the extremist support is high and variations large, then the econometrician 10

is likely to observe a negative correlation.

Figure 2: Degree of Strategic Voting as a Function of Extremist Support Note that Proposition 3 implies that the probability of centrist victory, is decreasing in θ and increasing in w. The effect of an increase in extremist popularity on the probability of centrist victory is not obvious, since strategic voting may increase in response to an increase in extremist popularity. The following result show that adjustment in strategic voting has only second order effect on the probability of centrist victory.

p(σc∗ ),

Proposition 4. The probability of centrists winning is decreasing in the popularity of the extremist.

3.1

UK Elections in the Thatcher Years

We now present stylize facts on the UK elections during the last Conservative Era (1979 - 1997), which provide good anecdotal evidence in support of our 11

main results: Proposition 1 and 3. In particular, the popularity of the Conservative Party had the predicted effect on the split of votes between Labour and Liberal Democrats (LD), the two main oppositions to the Conservatives. The Conservative Party and in particular its leader, Margaret Thatcher, dominated UK politics in the 1980s. In 1979, the Conservative Party defeated the incumbent Labor Party in the general election, although at that time Margaret Thatcher was not the popular figure she later became. Four years later, the Conservatives won the reelection on a wave of popular support, thanks to the victory in the Falklands War as well as improved economic conditions. After another victory in 1987, Thatcher resigned in 1990 and was succeeded by John Major, who did not have the charisma of Thatcher. Our model suggests that in 1979, voters who oppose the Conservatives would have rallied behind either the Labour or the Liberal Democrats because of the moderate popularity of the Conservatives. And those voters would split the vote in 1983 due to the high popularity of the Conservatives. Noticing the weakness of the Conservatives in 1992, the ethical voters would have acted strategically in that election but only to a limited extent. The trend of the outcomes in these elections supports our conclusions.14 In 1979, the Labour/LD split of the center-left vote was 73 to 27 percent, which indicates a high degree of strategic voting. In 1983, it was an almost even split, 52 to 48 percent. In 1992, the split was 66 to 34 percent, which suggests some degree of strategic voting, but not as high as the one registered in 1979. Empirical studies on these elections also lead to the same conclusions. For example, Heath and Evans (1994) estimate that strategic voting accounted for 9% of the vote in the 1992 election, while Johnston and Pattie (1991) find that it only accounted for 5.1% of all voters in 1983. 14

In the UK, each Member of Parliament represents a separate constituency. However, the panorama of the national vote (in particular, the swing in the vote) is widely used in the UK as an indicator of the swing in embattled constituencies.

12

4 4.1

Extensions Heterogeneity in w

So far, the centrist voters attach the same utility for the outcome of the election (i.e. the voter obtains w regardless of which centrists wins). In general, a centrist voter may feel differently about the center-left candidate winning and the center-right candidate winning. Let wl : [0, 1] → R++ and wr : [0, 1] → R++ be two functions, where wl (x) and wr (x) are the utilities that voter x receives when the center-left and the center-right candidate wins, respectively. Observe that, since there is a continuum of voters, the outcome cannot be affected by a single voter. Thus, partisan voters still vote for the candidate closer to their ideal point. The ethical voting rule, on the other hand, depends on the distribution of wl and wr . In particular, the objective function F (σc ) is: θ p(σc )E(wr ) − (σc2 − σc + 2 θ p(σc )E(wl ) − (σc2 − σc + 2

1 )− 2 1 )− 2

θ 8 θ 8

∀σc ≤

1 2

otherwise

F is not symmetric around 12 , unless E(wr ) = E(wl ). More specifically, the ethical voting rule σc∗ belongs to [0, 12 ] if E(wr ) > E(wl ) and [ 12 , 1] if E(wr ) < E(wl ). Ethical voters simply rally behind the candidate whose victory provides the highest aggregate utility (for the centrist voters). Hence, unlike the main model, ethical voters will no longer be indifferent between supporting the center-right or the center-left. It is straightforward to see that the characterization of the solution and the comparative statics with regard to θ and k˜e will not be affected by this

13

generalization.15 Comparative statics with respect to E(wr ) and E(wl ) are straightforward, keep in mind that one should interpret max{E(wr ), E(wl )} as the the importance of the election.

4.2

Turnout Decision

Suppose now the centrist voters also have to face a cost of turnout. In particular, suppose that the cost for a voter of going to the polls is θt, where t is a uniform random variable over [0, 1] independent of x. We assume the scaling factor θ is the same for x and t for simpliicty. In sum, the voters are now uniformly distributed in the space [0, 1]2 , where one dimension represents the expressive cost and the other the turnout cost. Given the above, it is easy to check that the ethical voting rule will be a constant 0 ≤ σc ≤ 2 such that all those voters for which (1 − x) + t ≤ σc will vote for the center-right candidate or abstain otherwise. This means that, contrary to the case with no turnout cost, it is possible that some voters with a strong preference for the center-right will not vote while those who prefer the center-left will do so, as long as the former have a higher turnout cost than the latter. Hence, the model with turnout costs implies that it is possible to observe, in the same election, a certain degree of strategic voting and significant abstention from the supporters of the party that is receiving those strategic votes. While we will not present the complete characterization of the problem with turnout costs, it is still convenient to portray the basic characteristics of the problem that ethical voters face. These will show the reader that the nature and structure of the problem does not change. As before, ethical 15

Simply take max{E(wl ), E(wr )} as w and when E(wl ) > E(wr ), the statement of the result should be modified to reflect the fact that σ ∗ ∈ [ 12 , 1] is the optimal solution.

14

voters select a rule σc that maximizes the expected social welfare of their group. However, since voters are distributed in the space [0, 1]2 , for a given σc , the expressions for the probability that a centrist candidate wins, p(σc ), and the cost of voting for the centrist group, C(σc ), are as follows: ( p(σc ) =

˜

max(1 − 2 σke2 , 0)

if 0 ≤ σc ≤ 1

˜e 2k 2−(2−σc )2

if 1 ≤ σc ≤ 2

c

1−

3

( C(σc ) =

θ( σc (σ2c +3)

θ σ3c 3 − σc3+4 )

if 0 ≤ σc ≤ 1 if 1 ≤ σc ≤ 2

(1)

(2)

The main difference between this setup and the one with no turnout is the change in slope of p(σc ) and C(σc ) when σc = 1. However, the expressions that correspond to when σc is between 0 and 1 are not relevant as the optimal σc will either be 0 or be in the interval [1, 2]. When σc ∈ [0, 1], at most half of the centrists are voting. Thus, given the restrictions on ke , centrists would be defeated with certainty. This means that ethical voters would be better off by abstaining completely. Hence, the range of the solution is similar to the one observed in the problem with no turnout costs, in which the ethical voting rule lies in [0, 1 − k˜e ) ∪ { 21 }. Moreover, the fact that σc∗ cannot be in the interval [0, 1] implies that if turnout from ethical voters increases, the fraction of agents engaging in strategic voting will also increase.

5

Conclusions

In this paper, we construct an ethical voters model to the study strategic voting. The model is parsimonious and provides a clear mechanism to explain when and to what degree strategic voting occurs. Our results shed light on 15

puzzling observations. In particular, we are able to show how an increase in the popularity of the extremist candidate can lead to either an increase or a decrease in the degree of strategic voting, depending on the initial values of electoral parameters. The tractability of the ethical voter framework means that potentially interesting modifications can be carried out. For example, a model with an arbitrary number of candidates may be worth examining. While established democracies like the Canada and the UK have three main parties, this is not the case for several developing democracies. It may also be fruitful to extend the model to a dynamic setting, where one can examine the incentives to form coalitions for parties that derive their support from the same subset of the electorate. The present study is an example of how ethical voter models can constitute useful alternatives to previous theories. In general, ethical agents can be used to explain how individuals act in contexts where an individual’s action has negligible impact on the outcome. Therefore, ethical agent models may prove useful for the analysis of collective phenomena such as consumer boycotts, mass rallies and recycling. As is the case for strategic voting, it is possible that the application of ethical agent models to these contexts leads to new insights that previous theories cannot provide.

References Abramson, Paul R., John H. Aldrich Phil Paolino, and David W. Rohde. 1992. ““Sophisticated” Voting in the 1988 Presidential Primaries.” The American Political Science Review, 86(1): 55–69. Alvarez, R. Michael, and Jonathan Nagler. 2000. “A New Approach for Modelling Strategic Voting in Multiparty Elections.” British Journal 16

of Political Science, 30(1): 57–75. Austen-Smith, David, and Jeffrey S. Banks. 2005. Positive Political Theory II: Strategy and Structure. Ann Arbor:University of Michigan Press. Blais, Andre. 2000. To Vote or Not to Vote: The Merits and Limits of Rational Choice Theory. Pittsburgh:University of Pittsburgh Press. Blais, Andre, and Richard Nadeau. 1996. “Measuring Strategic Voting: A Two-Step Procedure.” Electoral Studies, 15(1): 39–52. Brennan, Geoffrey. 2001. “Five Rational Actor Accounts of the Welfare State.” Kyklos, 54(2-3): 213–234. Cain, Bruce E. 1978. “Strategic Voting in Britain.” American Journal of Political Science, 22(3): 639–655. Coate, Stephen, and Michael Conlin. 2004. “A Group Rule-Utilitarian Approach to Voter Turnout: Theory and Evidence.” American Economic Review, 94(5): 1476–1504. Cox, Gary W. 1987. “Electoral Equilibrium under Alternative Voting Institutions.” American Journal of Political Science, 31(1): 82–108. Cox, Gary W. 1994. “Strategic Voting Equilibria Under the Single Nontransferable Vote.” The American Political Science Review, 88(3): 608–621. Cox, Gary W. 1997. Making Votes Count: Strategic Coordination in the World’s Electoral Systems. Cambridge:Cambridge University Press. Feddersen, Timothy, and Alvaro Sandroni. 2006a. “A Theory of Participation in Elections.” American Economic Review, 96(4): 1271–1282. Feddersen, Timothy, and Alvaro Sandroni. 2006b. “The Calculus of Ethical Voting.” International Journal of Game Theory, 35(1): 1–25. 17

Feddersen, Timothy, Sean Gailmard, and Alvaro Sandroni. 2009. “Moral Bias in Large Elections: Theory and Experimental Evidence.” American Political Science Review, 103(2): 175–192. Fey, Mark. 1997. “Stability and Coordination in Duverger’s Law: A Formal Model of Preelection Polls and Strategic Voting.” American Political Science Review, 91(1): 135–147. Fischer, A.J. 1996. “A Further Experimental Study of Expressive Voting.” Public Choice, 88(1-2): 171–184. Fisher, Stephen D. 2000. “Intuition versus Formal Theory: Tactical Voting in England 1987-1997.” Paper presented at the APSA meeting in Washington DC. Galbraith, John W., and Nicol C. Rae. 1989. “A Test of the Importance of Tactical Voting: Great Britain, 1987.” British Journal of Political Science, 19(1): 126–136. Harsanyi, John. 1977. “Morality and the Theory of Rational Behavior.” Social Research, 44(4): 623–656. Harsanyi, John. 1980. “Rule Utilitarianism, Rightrs, Obligations and the Theory of Rational Behavior.” Theory and Decision, 12(2): 115–133. Heath, Anthony, and Geoffrey Evans. 1994. “Tactical Voting: Concepts, Measurements and Findings.” British Journal of Political Science, 24(4): 557–561. Johnston, R.J., and C.J. Pattie. 1991. “Tactical Voting in Great Britain in 1983 and 1987: An Alternative Approach.” British Journal of Political Science, 21(1): 95–108.

18

Kan, Kamhon, and C.C. Yang. 2001. “On Expressive Voting: Evidence from the 1988 U.S. Presidential Election.” Public Choice, 108(3-4): 295– 312. Laband, David N., Ram Pandit John P. Sophocleus, and Anne M. Laband. 2009. “Patriotism, Pigskins and Politics: An Empirical Examination of Expressive Behavior and Voting.” Public Choice, 138(1-2): 97–108. Lanoue, David J., and Shaun Bowler. 1992. “The Sources of Tactical Voting in British Parliamentary Elections 1983-1987.” Political Behavior, 14(2): 141–157. Milgrom, Paul, and Chris Shannon. 1994. “Monotone Comparative Statics.” Econometrica, 62(1): 157–180. Myatt, David. 2007. “On the Theory of Strategic Voting.” Review of Economic Studies, 74(1): 255–281. Myerson, Roger B. 2002. “Comparison of Scoring Rules in Poisson Voting Games.” Journal of Economic Theory, 103(1): 219–251. Myerson, Roger B., and Robert J. Weber. 1993. “A Theory of Voting Equilibria.” The American Political Science Review, 87(1): 102–114. Niemi, Richard, Guy Whitten, and Mark N. Franklin. 1992. “Constituency Characteristics, Individual Characteristics and Tactical Voting in the 1987 British General Election.” British Journal of Political Science, 22(2): 229–240. Palfrey, Thomas. 1977. “A Mathematical Proof of Duverger’s Law.” Models of Strategic Choice in Politics, 44(4): 623–656. Picketty, Thomas. 2000. “Voting as Communicating.” The Review of Economic Studies, 67(1): 169–191.

19

Piolatto, Amedeo, and Florian Schuett. 2012. “Ethical Voters and the Demand for Political News.” https://sites.google.com/site/schuettflorian/. Spenkuch, Jorg. 2013. “On the Extent of Strategic http://kellogg.northwestern.edu/faculty/spenkuch/.

A

Voting.”

Mathematical Appendix

Proposition 1 Proof. Since 1−

k˜e − 12 1 ≤ 0 ∀σc ∈ [1 − k˜e , ], 1 2 − σc 2

the objective function becomes F (σc ) = − 2θ (σc2 −σc + 12 )− 8θ within the interval [1 − k˜e , 21 ], and it is maximized at 12 . Therefore, one can reduce the choice domain of the maximization problem to [0, 1 − k˜e ) ∪ { 21 }. The solution to the maximization problem can be found by first finding the optimal solution σ ˜c on the interval [0, 1 − k˜e ]. If σ ˜c = 1 − ke , then the global optimum is σc∗ = 12 since F (1 − k˜e ) < − 4θ = F ( 12 ). Otherwise, a comparison between F (˜ σc ) and F ( 21 ) determines the global optimum. It is easy to verify that the second order derivative of F within the interval [0, 1 − k˜e ] is negative because k˜e > 21 and σc < 12 . Consequently, the first order condition is sufficient and necessary for σ ˜c . Let F ∗ (w, θ, k˜e ) = maxσc ∈[0,1−k˜e ] F . By Berge’s theorem, F ∗ is continuous in its arguments, in particular it is continuous in k˜e . We will show below the existence of a k˜e for which F ∗ exceed − 4θ and another k˜e for which F ∗ is less than − 4θ . This will allow us to apply the intermediate value theorem and

20

conclude there exist k¯e such that F ∗ (w, θ, k¯e ) = − 4θ = F (σc = 12 ). And this k¯e is the threshold we desire because F ∗ is also monotonic in k˜e . It is straightforward to see that for k˜e sufficiently low, F ∗ (w, θ, k˜e ) > − 4θ = F (σc = 21 ). Next, we would like to show that the reverse inequality holds for sufficiently high k˜e . Note that the inequality F ∗ (w, θ, k˜e ) < − 4θ is necessary and sufficient condition for 12 being optimum, and a sufficient condition for the optimality of 21 is: θ − ≥ max {wp(σc )} − min 4 σc ∈[0,1−k˜e ] σc ∈[0,1−k˜e ]

   θ 1 θ 2 σc − σc + − 2 2 8

   Because 12 = argminσc ∈[0, 1 ] { 2θ σc2 − σc + 12 }, minσc ∈[0,1−k˜e ] 2θ σc2 − σc + 12 = 2 θ +  for some positive . Additionally, maxσc ∈[0,1−k˜e ] {wp(σc )} = w(2 − 2k˜2 ). 8 Rewriting the sufficient condition, we have: θ  θ − ≥ w(2 − 2k˜2 ) − −  ⇐⇒ k˜e ≥ 1 − 4 4 2w Thus, for k˜e sufficiently high, − 4θ .

1 2

is the optimum and equivalently, F ∗ (w, θ, k˜e ) <

Corollary 1 Proof. Observe that F ∗ is increasing in w and decreasing in θ, and to satisfy F ∗ (w, θ, k¯e ) = − 4θ , k¯e must increase in w and decrease in θ. Proposition 2  Proof. Note first that, F (0) ≥ F ( 12 ) ⇐⇒ w 1 − 21

˜e − 1 k 2 1 2





θ 4

≥ − 8θ ⇐⇒

θ θ ≥ k˜e . This implies that 1 − 16w ≥ k˜e is sufficient for strategic voting. 1 − 16w ˜ −1) w(k Furthermore, if 1 + θ ≤ k˜e , then ∂F (0) = − e1 2 + θ ≤ 0. This means that 2

8w

∂σc

4

2

for + ≤ k˜e , σ ∗ < 12 =⇒ σ ∗ = 0. Thus, the first result follows because 1 θ θ θ + 8w ≤ 1 − 16w ⇐⇒ wθ ≤ 83 . It also follows that for wθ ≥ 38 , 12 + 8w < k˜e is 2 a sufficient condition for vote splitting. However, this condition is vacuous p for wθ ≥ 4. We will now show that k˜e > 12 + wθ is a sufficient condition for vote splitting, and this will complete our proof.   ke − 21 1−ke ˜ Observe that on the interval [0, 1 − ke ], F (σc ) = w 1 − 1 −σc − 2θ (σc2 − 1 2

θ 8w

2

dF σc + − is a strictly concave function . It means that if dσ (1 − k˜e ) ≥ 0, c 1 is the global optimum since F ( 12 ) > F (1 − k˜e ) ≥ F (σc ) ∀σc ∈ [0, 1 − k˜e ). 2 Now, 1 ) 2

θ 8

w(k˜e − 21 ) θ dF (1 − k˜e ) = − 1 − θ(1 − k˜e ) + dσc 2 ( 2 − k˜e )2 =−

w ˜ ke −

1 2

θ − θ(1 − k˜e ) + 2

and − k˜ w− 1 −θ(1−k˜e )+ 2θ ≥ 0 ⇐⇒ k˜e2 −k˜e + 14 − wθ ≥ 0. Apply the quadratic e 2 √ √ 4w 1+ 4w θ ˜e ≤ 1− θ , the derivative of F is formula, we see that for k˜e ≥ and k 2 2 √ 1− 4w θ ˜ positive. However, note that it cannot be the case ke ≤ since k˜e > 12 2 by assumption.

Proposition 3 Proof. We shall use the monotone comparative statics results from Milgrom & Shannon (1994): If the cross derivative of F with respect to the choice variable (i.e. σc ) and the parameter of interest, and if the cross partial 22

is positive (negative), then the solution is increasing (decreasing) in that ke − 21 e , it follows parameter. Observe that for σ ∗ ∈ [0, 1 − k˜e ), p(σc ) = 1 − 1−k 1 c

that

∂2F ∂w∂σc

< 0,

∂2F ∂θ∂σc

> 0 and

∂2F ˜e ∂σc ∂k

2

−σc

< 0.

Proposition 4 Proof. When 0 < σc∗ <

1 , 2

the first order conditions characterizes the opr   1 1 3 w ∗ ˜ ke − 2 . timum and the following expression is obtained: σc = 2 − θ − 23  ∗ w 1 w ˜ c Thus, we see that ∂σ = − ( k − ) . From the expression for the e ˜e 3θ θ 2 ∂k probability of the center winning the election, we obtain: ∗ 1 c − σc∗ + (k˜e − 12 ) ∂σ ∂p(σc∗ ) ˜e 2 ∂k =− ( 12 − σc∗ )2 ∂ k˜e



c Replacing our previous values for σc∗ and ∂σ ˜e , we obtain that the numer∂k r   ator is equal to 23 3 wθ k˜e − 12 > 0. Since the denominator is also positive

and the fraction is multiplied by -1, we get the probability of winning is decreasing when σ ∗ is interior. The results extends easily to the case where σ ∗ = 0 (refer to Proposition 1 and 2)

23

Ethical Motives for Strategic Voting

Jan 17, 2014 - θ(1−x) for voting for the center-right.10 We interpret θ as the degree of par- .... ke (call it. ¯ ke) such that the ethical voters split their votes (i.e. σ∗ c = 1 .... with turnout costs, it is still convenient to portray the basic characteristics.

313KB Sizes 3 Downloads 237 Views

Recommend Documents

Mixed Motives and the Optimal Size of Voting Bodies - CiteSeerX
In large vot- ing bodies, the chance of a single vote being decisive is negligible, and ex- pressive motives come to the fore. Finally, for bodies of intermediate size, ... as long as passion and reason are correlated, we show that “passionate” v

Inferring Strategic Voting
16 We assume that voter beliefs over three-way ties are infinitesimal ..... the Japanese Diet and there is little variation in the roll call vote within a given party.

Mixed Motives and the Optimal Size of Voting Bodies - CiteSeerX
The University of Chicago Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Journal of Political .... long history in political economy. ...... Pittsburgh. Brennan, Geoffrey, and James Buchanan. 1984. “Voter Choice: Evalu

Ethical altruistic voting in a multi-ethnic developing ...
tween egoism and ethical altruism and predict, according to the degree of ethical altruism, the ... Ethiopia, ethnic federalism, ethnicity, public good, voting behaviour ... among them, a just administration tempers conflicts between various interest

Ethical altruistic voting in a multi-ethnic developing ...
Ethiopia, ethnic federalism, ethnicity, public good, voting behaviour. JEL code: D02 .... as a "class manipulation and mobilisation of the ethnic sentiments for purely ...... ios where an ethnicity-oriented party wins the majority on its own. In case

MOTIVES
For our purposes here, we will review, as an introduction to the topic of ...... of X. Let M be a virtual pure motives of a smooth projective variety X, i.e, ...... projection π : B(V ) → C. This is an algebraic variety, from which one can read ph

Strategic, Sincere, and Heuristic Voting under Four ...
Jan 17, 2010 - featuring 63 subjects8), eight in Montreal, Canada (of which four .... The pictures for AV and STV do not show any time-dependence effect.

Strategic Voting in Multi-Winner Elections with Approval ...
Jul 21, 2016 - the possibility of three-way ties; a cognitive assumption which .... is the candidate whose expected score is the M-th largest — we will call this.

Strategic Voting in a Social Context: Considerate ...
The speci- ficity of our work is that we embed the voting game into a social context where agents and their relations are given by a graph, i.e. a social network.

Auto-verifying voting system and voting method
Feb 14, 2005 - mechanical or electronic comparison of the printed ballot with the data stored from the voter input. The present invention has elements that may be consid ered to be covered generally by class 235, particularly sub class 51 covering ma

Maps for Early Voting Report.pdf
Austin Community College CPPPS Report #5. Appendix of Maps ... Tarrant. Taylor. Terrell. Terry Throckmorton Titus. Tom Green. Travis. Trinity. Tyler. Upshur.

Auto-verifying voting system and voting method
Feb 14, 2005 - in memory or on storage media. A printed ballot produced by the computer voting station which shows the votes of a voter is then presented to the voter and either compared by the voter, or by operation of the computer program for the v

Egalitarian Motives in Humans Supplementary ...
are willing to pay for costly taking and giving even when the norm enforcement motive is eliminated, and ... (6) as a “baseline” level of non-egalitarian taking and giving that occurs under any circumstances, but these ... implication is that ine

Voting Systems
Florida,. 1 and in 2004, the dispute over counting votes in Ohio sparked members of ... First, because of the Electoral College, George Bush won the election even though ... First, for a vote to count, all voters must cast an equally effective vote.

The Brauer group of 1-motives
May 3, 2017 - M as the Brauer group of the associated Picard S-stack M, i.e.. Br(M) := Br(M). ...... A Series of Modern Surveys in Mathematics, 39. Springer-.

MULTILINEAR MORPHISMS BETWEEN 1-MOTIVES ...
Observe that the tensor product M1⊗M2 of two 1-motives is not defined yet, and ...... corresponds to the identities morphisms idM1 : M1 → M1 and idM∗. 1. : M∗.

Voting Systems
... note 34, at 491; Unofficial Election Returns, THE DAILY MINING JOURNAL (Marquette, ... 53 A study using 1982 data found that, “[n]early 60% of all U.S. cities with .... a choice of vanilla or chocolate ice cream, and the customer chooses.

Voting for children's book awards opens Nov. 1 Voting opens Nov. 1 ...
Oct 31, 2014 - Voting opens Nov. 1 for the Prairie Bud and Prairie Pasque Children's Book Awards, sponsored by the South Dakota Library Association.

Voting for children's book awards opens Nov. 1 Voting opens Nov. 1 ...
Oct 31, 2014 - Winning books will be announced in April during National Library Week. South Dakota educators select nominees, which include literary and informational texts. Learn more about the nominees here. The award website also includes valuable

The Brauer group of 1-motives
May 3, 2017 - Notation. 3. 1. Recall on Sheaves, Gerbes and Picard Stacks on a Stack. 5. 2. ... defined over a scheme S. We proceed in the following way: Let X be ..... We call the pair (U, u) an open of X with respect to the choosen topology.

the functional autonomy of motives
we see the rising tide of interest in problems of personality. Up to a .... Such a theory is obviously opposed to psychoanalysis and to all other genetic accounts.

Voting Pads.pdf
identify which answers have come from which handset. To do this you must make a 'Participant List'. To make a 'Participant List' you will need the Device ID, ...

Voting Flier.pdf
the school election. 3. BRYAN HARMS AND LEANDRA FERNANDEZ FALL 2016. Does your vote count? High Tech Middle Chula Vista, 8th grade. Page 1 of 2 ...

Blockholder Voting
academic and regulatory debate (Coffee and Palia, 2015). In this paper, we study .... against management, and 13% publicly criticized management in the media. These forms of public ..... from a successful activism campaign. .... social welfare.