Phenom Cogn Sci (2009) 8:279–283 DOI 10.1007/s11097-009-9142-6

Dimensions of bodily subjectivity D. Legrand & T. Grünbaum & J. Krueger

Published online: 5 August 2009 # Springer Science + Business Media B.V. 2009

There has been a recent resurgence of interest in the body both within philosophical as well as cognitive scientific approaches to consciousness and cognition. An abundance of body-centric alliterative characterizations now abound throughout the literature. It is widely argued, for instance, that mind is only to be understood once we take seriously its fundamentally ecological, or situated, character. From this general orientation, we then encounter further claims: mind is embodied, embedded, enacted, and, most radically of all, extended. However, at the heart of these approaches lies the embodiment thesis. In its leanest formulation, this is the thesis that mental activity depends essentially not just on the brain but on the body as well. There is an emerging consensus that philosophical and empirical investigations of cognition must therefore begin with a consideration of the contribution of the body to our interactions with the world. But what sort of body are we talking about, exactly? If mind is essentially embodied, how are we to understand the nature of this “body” and its central role in driving mental activity? There are multiple ways of approaching this question. For instance, one may talk about the physiological body, while another may be interested in the experiential body; one may consider the functional body while D. Legrand (*) Centre de Recherche en Epistémologie Appliquée, CREA–ENSTA, 32 Boulevard Victor, 75015 Paris, France e-mail: [email protected] T. Grünbaum Department of Media, Cognition, and Communication, Philosophy Section, University of Copenhagen, Njalsgade 140-142, 2300 Copenhagen, Denmark e-mail: [email protected] J. Krueger Danish National Research Foundation, Center for Subjectivity Research, University of Copenhagen, Njalsgade 140-142, 2300 Copenhagen, Denmark e-mail: [email protected]

280

D. Legrand et al.

another would insist on a strictly biological conception of the body; one may be interested in the relation between the anatomical body and the experiential body, while another may focus on the represented body; one may be interested in bodily self-consciousness, while another may insist on the priority of intersubjective bodily encounter; one may intend to determine our bodily power of constituting our world transcendentally, thereby rejecting the view of the body as being in the midst of things out there in the world, while others may have a more realist understanding of the body as our primary mode of being-in-the-world. The purpose of this special issue is not to provide the comprehensive definition of the body. This is certainly a fruitless aspiration. For the body, as the papers below make quite clear, is indeed a many-splendored thing. Thus, approaching the body as though it were a singular entity is a non-starter. The body is plural; it harbors multiple dimensions. And the goal of this special issue is therefore to participate in the development of a fine-grained description of the body in its rich multidimensionality. Thanks to careful conceptual analysis, and informed by empirical data from cognitive psychology and neurosciences, as well as clinical data from neurology, the authors represented here all investigate the body in a way that honors its physiological and experiential complexity. In doing so, they stretch the boundaries of what is commonly called “body”. Gunnar Declerck and Olivier Gapenne argue that the actual state of one’s body does not exhaust the complexity of the body’s relation to its world: one also needs to consider bodily possibilities. Declerck and Gapenne consider how such possibilities are available in different kinds of world-directed actions. By relying on empirical data, they argue that the perception of the spatial structure of one’s environment is determined not only by the perceiver’s action but, moreover, by the perceiver’s possibilities for action. Thereby, the world appears perceptually to the bodily agent as a meaning-laden environment, that is, as a world affording possible actions. Stretching the boundary of the body as classically defined, the authors here defend a view of the body as defined by its practical engagement with the world. Helena De Preester and Manos Tsakiris tackle the body–world engagement at the point where it reaches its limit: when an element of the world becomes a part of one's body. More specifically, they discuss the distinction between two forms of body modulation: body extension (e.g., with prostheses) and incorporation of noncorporeal items into the body (e.g., tools). De Preester and Tsakiris argue that such modulations are possibilities inherent to bodily subjectivity. These possibilities characterize human beings as embodied beings whose boundaries are not fixed but rather plastic and vulnerable. On this basis, the authors rely on recent empirical findings (mostly on the so-called Rubber Hand Illusion) to argue for three theses: (1) incorporation involves body-ownership over the incorporated item, while body extension would not involve such experience; (2) body-ownership is determined both by bottom-up multisensory integration and top-down body representation; and (3) body plasticity is limited according to this pre-existing and normative body representation. The first two papers affirm that bodily experience is a dynamically plastic and, at times, open-ended affair. But there are constraints on bodily experience. For, while wearing prostheses can involve the incorporation of non-bodily objects into one's body, and while a rubber hand stimulated simultaneously with one's own may be felt

Dimensions of bodily subjectivity

281

as if it were, in fact, one’s own hand, it nevertheless remains the case that, paradigmatically, we recognize our own body as our own and another’s body as theirs—and we do this without confusing one for the other. When I shake another person’s hand, for example, I immediately know which hand is mine. Jenny Slatman explores this phenomenon of bodily self-recognition by summoning conceptual resources from both Husserl and Merleau-Ponty’s phenomenological analyses of embodiment. Slatman characterizes bodily self-recognition as involving a direct experience of one's lived body together with one's mediated experience of one's physical body as objective. This intersection of the subjective and physical dimensions of one's body, in other words, is what explains the fact that we see ourselves in a mirror—and not merely an alien image. Slatman thus characterizes the self as involving both a “here” (i.e., the point where my body anchors my experiential perspective on the world) and a “there” (i.e., the point where I can see my body in the midst of the world). On the other hand, others would be recognized as being merely “there” in a world that we share. The body clearly plays a central role in shaping our social encounters. Jonathan Cole explores this bodily basis of intersubjectivity. By chronicling the narratives of individuals with different sorts of bodily (dis)abilities, Cole affirms the centrality of the body as agent for social and personal expression and self-esteem. In particular, he considers the double impact of several neurological impairments. These impairments affect not only the way one deals with and experiences one's body. They also affect the way that one can or cannot encounter others and live in a society where one's bodily (dis)abilities are marginalized or misunderstood. Cole examines the experiences of people suffering from impairment of movement and sensation, deafferentation, severe spinal cord injury, and Möbius syndrome (the congenital absence of facial expression). Cole finds that a recurrent issue for them all is the struggle to cope with their body in a way that manages to open an inclusive social space—a space where they can express, experience, and share with others (‘able bodies’) in mutually satisfying ways. Cole also finds that whether one's bodily impairment is lived positively or not depends not only on one's relation to one's body per se (e.g., whether one manages to cope with or compensate for the impairment), but also—and crucially on one's relation to others through each other's body. Cole’s paper thus affirms both the bodily and dialectical nature of our social life. Being essentially social through bodily encounters with others, one must rely on the constant understanding of others as being not only bodies but subjects. Cole’s paper vividly shows the social difficulties encountered by people suffering from bodily impairments. John Stins and Steven Laureys tackle a different but related difficulty. They ask: when confronted with a brain-damaged body, deprived of any means of communication, can we detect signs of conscious mental life? How, if at all, can we communicate with unresponsive patients? If a body is perceptually accessible only in its physicality, how can we detect its simultaneous subjectivity? Stins and Laureys describe the standard clinical approach to determine whether or not a patient is conscious as being an equivalent of the Turing test: the aim is to establish whether or not there is mental life behind the behavioral responses to external probing (questions, commands, tests). Facing patients suffering from coma, vegetative state, or locked-in syndrome, however, Stins and Laureys cannot rely on any potential motor responsiveness. Since they are unable to ask the patients to give

282

D. Legrand et al.

reports about their mental states, they turn instead to the brain and take a new look at brain signals. These signals are not read as putative signatures of mental states per se; rather, they are treated as behavioral responses, in that they suggest that the patient's brain is reactive to verbal instructions in a coherent, stable, and fine-grained manner. On this basis, Stins and Laureys report the possibility to develop brain– computer interfaces which would be usable as communication devices by braindamaged people. The confrontation with pathological cases, and the difficulty of interpreting them accurately, poses important methodological problems. The consequences of such problems are clinical and ethical, as Stins and Laureys report. And they are also conceptual, as Rasmus Thybo Jensen shows in his paper. Thybo Jensen focuses on Merleau-Ponty’s interpretation and use of the so-called Schneider case. He uncovers a shortcoming in Merleau-Ponty’s report of the case, and a potential ambiguity in its use: indeed, when compared to normal subjects, one and the same case is interpreted as involving either the preservation or the impairment of motor intentionality. While seemingly contradictory at first glance, these two interpretations in fact complete each other. In particular, Thybo Jensen argues that Schneider’s condition is best characterized by a disintegration of two intentional attitudes that normally modulate one another: the concrete (which informs habitual, context-bound actions like swatting away a mosquito or removing and lighting a match), and the abstract (bending and straightening a finger upon request, describing the position of one’s body). Schneider’s case in particular, according to Thybo Jensen, thus sheds light on the general difficulty of interpreting pathological cases with the aim of better understanding normal functioning. For, beyond the mere dichotomy of preservation and impairment, there is room for a consideration of some pathologies as involving a reorganization of the system at stake, a variation of the total bodily being of the subject. While phenomenology often uses pathological cases as a window on the variability of experiences, the use of expert cases is less common. Dorothée Legrand and Susanne Ravn argue, however, that relying on bodily expertise potentially opens up new understandings of bodily self-consciousness. Legrand and Ravn consider the experience of different groups of dancers. They investigate how such “body experts” may experience the subjectivity of their own body by paying attention to objectified elements such as a visual image of themselves, or to nonbodily elements such as music that guides their dancing. The possibility of such “subjective perception” of one’s body is revealing, the authors argue. For, it discloses important lessons about the very nature of the body: far from being divided as classical phenomenology assumes, the body's subjective and physical dimensions are united in one's bodily self-consciousness. Rather than offering up sweeping conclusions or far-reaching generalizations, this special issue on Dimensions of Bodily Subjectivity hopes instead simply to continue the momentum behind many recent developments in this protean enterprise of “embodied cognition”. Given the rapid growth of this field—and as the different perspectives represented in these papers collectively affirm—working toward a better understanding of the complexity of the body itself is indeed a timely project. For, while researchers of all stripes are eager to embrace an “embodied” approach— or conversely, to mount challenges against the perceived excesses of embodied

Dimensions of bodily subjectivity

283

views of cognition—there has often been little effort to define what sort of body is under consideration. Conceptual clarification is thus sorely needed if progress is to be made in this dynamic field. It is the hope of the editors that this special issue meaningfully contributes to this project. Acknowledgments DL acknowledges the support of the CNCC program of the European Science Foundation for founding the conference ESPRA2 (Copenhagen, 2008), conference where participants tackled dimensions of bodily subjectivity, and whose contributions are included in the present special issue. DL also acknowledges the support of the “European Platform for Life Sciences, Mind Sciences, and the Humanities” grant by the Volkswagen Stiftung for the ‘‘Body-Project: interdisciplinary investigations on bodily experiences”. TG acknowledges the support of the ESF eurocore program ‘BASIC’ and the Danish Research Counsel for the Humanities (FKK). JK acknowledges the support of the Danish National Research Foundation (DNRF).

Dimensions of bodily subjectivity - PhilArchive

Aug 5, 2009 - honors its physiological and experiential complexity. ... does not exhaust the complexity of the body's relation to its world: one also needs to.

77KB Sizes 4 Downloads 259 Views

Recommend Documents

Dimensions of bodily subjectivity - PhilArchive
Aug 5, 2009 - findings (mostly on the so-called Rubber Hand Illusion) to argue for three theses: (1) incorporation involves ... (3) body plasticity is limited according to this pre-existing and normative body representation. The first two ... ourselv

Perceiving subjectivity in bodily movement: The case of ...
Published online: 16 June 2009. © Springer Science + Business Media B.V. 2009 ... We will start by specifying the form of experience of the body that is at stake here .... own body; my body is then equivalent to others′ body (1943, pp 445, ...

innateness - PhilArchive
Aug 10, 2011 - data to which children are standardly exposed to determine the elaborate grammars that they quickly ..... particular developmental models and strategies. (See Griffiths ... close relation to the next conception we examine. 2.2.

Download - PhilArchive
Teoria delle grandezze, Pisa: Spoerri. [3] Bettazzi, Rodolfo (1891). 'Sui sistemi di numerazione per i numeri reali', Periodico di matematica per l'insegnamento ...

Why Care Final - PhilArchive
Why Justification Matters. Declan Smithies. Forthcoming in Epistemic Evaluation: Point and Purpose in Epistemology, edited by J. Greco and D. Henderson. Oxford University Press, 2015. Justification is one among many dimensions of epistemic evaluation

Rethinking Education - PhilArchive
In this series of posts I will break Mitra's Guardian article down and offer a critical response to each of his points. The first point I wish to address arises from this passage: "Any standard room in a Holiday Inn is better than the best facilities

8 Dimensions Of Excellence
majority of managers and professionals across all industries. ... Business process improvement. • Cycle time ... is merely one of the eight cylinders of the enter- prise engine we ... Product. © 2006, International Management Technologies Inc.

Drawing the line - PhilArchive
beliefs that interpret evidence on the basis of grater individual happiness (all other things being equal), this suggests that the basis of choice goes beyond rationality. I contend that the case against the rationality of cognitive therapy is not ma

Symmetry and Equivalence - PhilArchive
My topic is the relation between two notions, that of a symmetry of a physical theory and that of the physical equivalence of two solutions or models of such a theory. In various guises, this topic has been widely addressed by philosophers in recent

6 The nonconceptual content of experience - PhilArchive
definition: some of the states of a perceiver's visual system will have contents with ...... specifying a scenario: a set of ways of filling out the space around the.

Neuroethics, reductionism and dualism - PhilArchive
challenges the conventional wisdom that quantum fluctuations are always self-averaging, and goes ... Basic Books. 1364-6613/$ - see front matter Q 2005 ...

Neuroethics, reductionism and dualism - PhilArchive
5 Shobe, K.K. and Kihlstrom, J.F. (1997) Is traumatic memory special? ... Memory & Cognition 26, 3–19 ... contrary, several logical, empirical and philosophical.

The Nature of Cognitive Phenomenology - PhilArchive
phenomenal duplicates, but not intentional duplicates. Nevertheless ... prime number, then so is any phenomenal duplicate of mine. ..... Berlin: De Gruyter, 2012.

Phenomenal Basis of Epistemic Justification - PhilArchive
consciousness is the basis of epistemic justification and hence that the problem of explaining .... either to phenomenal consciousness or to functional role. In the ...

Why Care Final - PhilArchive
justified beliefs fall short of knowledge when they are false or when they are true but unreliable. Accordingly, one of the ... justification is the property that turns true belief into knowledge. But one lesson to be learned ..... corrupting influen

Different Flavours? - PhilArchive
With this distinction in mind, we can try to bridge the gulf between a wine's .... reflection of a wine's flavours we must turn to the suggestion of Haplern (1997) that.

Symmetry and Equivalence - PhilArchive
Unfortunately, these mutually reinforcing half-arguments don't add up to much: each ...... Torre, C. (1995), “Natural Symmetries and Yang–Mills Equations.” Jour-.

CONSCIOUSNESS, THE SELF, AND BODILY ...
meaning how could she have a conscious sensation of touches on her niece's hand. Plainly FB was aware of the sensation as her own, but also aware of it as.

Models as make-believe - PhilArchive
and Cohen ask us to suppose that we were to pick up a salt shaker and stipulate to our dinner partner that it represents Madagascar. As long as our stipulation is ...

Bodily Illusions Modulate Tactile Perception
se, that influences tactile processing. .... tion of touch might reflect a general process of cross- ..... parallel processing of tactual information in somatosensory.

Care of the self, resistance and subjectivity under neoliberal ...
Care of the self, resistance and subjectivity under neoliberal governmentalities.pdf. Care of the self, resistance and subjectivity under neoliberal ...