Journal of Economic Theory 106, 467–471 (2002) doi:10.1006/jeth.2001.2899

NOTES, COMMENTS, AND LETTERS TO THE EDITOR Beliefs and Pareto Efficient Sets: A Remark 1 Thibault Gajdos Université Cergy-Pontoise, THEMA; and EUREQua, Université Paris I, 106–112 bld de l’Hôpital, 75647 Paris Cedex 13, France [email protected]

and Jean-Marc Tallon 2 EUREQua, CNRS-Université Paris I, 106–112 bld de l’Hôpital, 75647 Paris Cedex 13, France; and Universita Ca’Foscari, Venezia, Italy [email protected] Received July 18, 2000; final version received March 20, 2001

We show that, in a two-period economy with uncertainty in the second period, if an allocation is Pareto optimal for a given set of beliefs and remains optimal when these beliefs are changed, then the set of optimal allocations of the two economies must actually coincide. We identify equivalence classes of beliefs, giving rise to the same set of Pareto optimal allocations. Journal of Economic Literature Classification Numbers: D51, D61. © 2002 Elsevier Science (USA) Key Words: beliefs; Pareto optimality.

1. INTRODUCTION In this Note, we seek to answer a very simple question: what can we learn about agents’ beliefs by the sole knowledge that a given allocation is Pareto optimal? More specifically, consider a multiple-goods, two-period 1 We thank E. Dekel, I. Gilboa, P. Gourdel, Z. Safra, and D. Schmeidler for useful comments and discussions. We are grateful to an anonymous referee for pointing out a mistake in an earlier draft. 2 To whom correspondence should be addressed. Financial support from the European Community (TMR Program) and the hospitality of Tel Aviv University, where part of this work has been done, are gratefully acknowledged.



467 0022-0531/02 $35.00 © 2002 Elsevier Science (USA) All rights reserved.

468

GAJDOS AND TALLON

economy with uncertainty in the second period and agents that are subjective expected utility maximizers. Take a Pareto optimal allocation of this economy. Is it possible that this allocation still be Pareto optimal in an economy in which agents’ beliefs have changed? We answer this question affirmatively and actually identify the exact change of beliefs needed. The result we obtain is actually stronger: if agent h’s subjective probability of state s divided by that of state s − in the second economy (i.e., the economy after beliefs have changed) is proportional (with the same coefficient of proportionality for all the agents) to the same ratio in the initial economy, then, the set of Pareto optimal allocations is the same in those two economies. We furthermore show that this is equivalent to the two sets of Pareto optimal allocations having one (interior) point in common. Hence, two contract curves associated to two economies with different beliefs are either equal or disjoint. To the best of our knowledge, this point, as simple as it seems, has not been studied in the literature. In a sense, the class of probabilities we identify is similar to what Radner [2] called ‘‘confounding’’ probabilities in a (rational expectations) equilibrium set-up, since in our set-up, two such sets of beliefs lead to the same Pareto optimal set.

2. THE SET UP AND MAIN RESULT We consider a standard two-period economy with uncertainty in the second period. There are H agents, h=1, ..., H and C commodities, c=1, ..., C, in each spot market. Without loss of generality we assume that there is no consumption in the first period. Uncertainty is represented by a state space S={1, ..., S}, with s ¥ S a state of nature. Total contingent CS endowments are given by e=(e(1), ..., e(S)) ¥ R+ +. Agents are subjective expected utility maximizers with beliefs ph = (ph (1), ..., ph (S)). It is assumed that ph (s) > 0 -s ¥ {1, ..., S} and, naturally CS that ; s ph (s)=1 for all h. Agent h has consumption set R+ + , certainty preferences represented by the von Neumann–Morgenstern utility index C uh : R+ + Q R. uh is assumed to be twice continuously differentiable, differentiably strictly increasing (i.e., Nuh (x) ± 0 for x ± 0) and differentiably strictly concave (i.e., Dx t N 2uh (x) Dx < 0 for x ± 0, Dx ] 0), and to C . Finally, the household have indifference surfaces with closures in R++ evaluates its contingent consumption plan, represented by the vector CS xh =(xh (1), ..., xh (S)) ¥ R+ + , according to the von Neumann–Morgenstern functional Vh (xh (1), ..., xh (S))=; s ph (s) uh (xh (s)). An allocation x=(x1 , ..., xH ) is feasible if xh (s) ± 0 for all h and all s and ; H h=1 xh (s)=e(s) for all s. An allocation x is Pareto optimal if there is

BELIEFS AND PARETO EFFICIENT SETS

469

no other feasible allocation x − such that Vh (x −h ) \ Vh (xh ) for all h and Vh (x −h ) > Vh (xh ) for some h. In this note, we take the von Neumann–Morgenstern utility indices and total endowments to be fixed and allow changes in agents’ beliefs. Let P(p) be the set of Pareto optima of the economy where agents have beliefs p=(p1 , ..., pH ). Recall that in our simple setup 3 an allocation x is a Pareto optimal allocation if and only if there exists a vector of weights l=(l1 , ..., lH ) ± 0 such that x is a solution to the problem S H max ; H h=1 lh ; s=1 ph (s) uh (xh (s)) s.t. ; h=1 xh (s)=e(s) for all s and xh ± 0 for all h. The main result of this note is to compare the set of Pareto optimal allocations in two economies differing only by the agents’ beliefs. Proposition 1. The following three assertions are equivalent: (i) P(p)=P(pˆ) (ii) P(p) 5 P(pˆ) ] ” p (s)/p (sŒ) pˆ (s)/pˆ (sŒ) (iii) -h, h −, -s, s −, phŒh (s)/phhŒ (sŒ)=pˆhŒh (s)/pˆhhŒ (sŒ) Proof. Recall first the following lemma (see, e.g., [1]): Lemma. A feasible allocation x is Pareto optimal if and only if there exist positive weights, lh > 0, all h, and strictly positive contingent goods prices (multipliers) for each state, m(s) ± 0, all s, such that lh ph (s) Nuh (xh (s))=m(s),

all h, s.

Let us now prove our result. That (i) implies (ii) is trivial. (ii) S (iii). Assume that P(p) 5 P(pˆ) ] ” and pick a feasible allocation x in P(p) 5 P(pˆ). Then, there exist l=(l1 , ..., lH ) ± 0 and lˆ=(lˆ1 , ..., lˆH ) ± 0 as well as m=(m(1), ..., m(S)) and mˆ=(mˆ(1), ..., mˆ(S)) such that, for all h, h − and all s: lh ph (s) Nuh (xh (s))=lhŒ phŒ (s) NuhŒ (xhŒ (s))=m(s) lˆh pˆh (s) Nuh (xh (s))=lˆhŒ pˆhŒ (s) NuhŒ (xhŒ (s))=mˆ(s). Hence, lh ph (s) lˆ pˆ (s) =ˆ h h , lhŒ phŒ (s) lhŒ pˆhŒ (s) 3

See for instance [1].

-h, h −, s.

470

GAJDOS AND TALLON

Therefore, for all s, s −, h and h −, ph (s) pˆhŒ (s) ph (s −) pˆhŒ (s −) = phŒ (s) pˆh (s) phŒ (s −) pˆh (s −) proving (iii). (iii) S (i). Let x ¥ P(p). Then, by the lemma, there exists a vector of weights l=(l1 , ..., lH ) ± 0 and multipliers (contingent goods prices) CS m=(m(1), ..., m(S)) ¥ R+ + such that, for all h and all s, lh ph (s) Nuh (xh (s))=m(s).

(1)

Now, by assumption, ph (s)/ph (1) pˆh (s)/pˆh (1) = p1 (s)/p1 (1) pˆ1 (s)/pˆ1 (1) for all h and all s. Hence, (1) is equivalent to lh

ph (1) p (1) pˆ1 (s) pˆ (s) Nuh (xh (s))= 1 m(s) pˆh (1) h p1 (s) pˆ1 (1)

for all h and all s. Therefore, defining lˆh =lh we get that

ph (1) pˆh (1)

p (1) pˆ (s)

and mˆ(s)=p11 (s) pˆ11(1) m(s),

lˆh pˆh (s) Nuh (xh (s))=mˆ(s) for all h and all s. Since lˆh > 0 and mˆ(s) > 0, this establishes (by the lemma above) that x ¥ P(pˆ). Therefore, P(p) ı P(pˆ). The converse inclusion also holds by a symmetric argument. Hence P(p)=P(pˆ). L Observe that condition (iii) in the proposition does not imply that ph =pˆh for all h, as shown by the following example: H=2, S=2, and p1 (1)=14 , p2 (1)=13 , pˆ1 (1)=13 ˆ 2 (1)=13 16 and p 15 . p (s) To interpret condition (iii), observe that the ratio phh(sŒ) is simply the marginal rate of substitution, say of good 1, between state s and s − when agent h is risk neutral (i.e., has a linear utility index). Alternatively, it is the marginal rate of substitution between state s and s − at points where the consumer is fully insured, i.e., consumes the same bundle in each of these states. CS CS Remark 1. If we were to take R+ rather than R+ + as households’ consumption set and extend the domain of the utility function accordingly, the same result would continue to hold, in which condition (ii) is replaced CSH by P(p) 5 P(pˆ) 5 R+ + ] ”.

BELIEFS AND PARETO EFFICIENT SETS

471

Remark 2. The framework developed can be reinterpreted in an intertemporal setting, with time-separable, time-independent preferences. Indeed, interpreting s as a time index and writing ph (s)=(bh ) s where bh is h’s stationary discount factor, our result says that if the discount factor changes but the ratios of the discount factors for any two agents remain the same, then the two economies have the same Pareto optima.

REFERENCES 1. D. Cass, G. Chichilnisky, and H.-M. Wu, Individual risk and mutual insurance, Econometrica 64 (1996), 333–341. 2. R. Radner, Rational expectations equilibrium: Generic existence and the information revealed by prices, Econometrica 47 (1979), 655–678.

Beliefs and Pareto Efficient Sets - Paris School of Economics

h's subjective probability of state s divided by that of state s− in the second .... (ii) S (iii). Assume that P(p) 5 P(p) ] ” and pick a feasible allocation x in P(p) 5 P(p).

79KB Sizes 0 Downloads 250 Views

Recommend Documents

Market Efficiencies and Market Risks - Paris School of Economics
sulting quality of the information efficiency of the market: homogenous agents lead to good information ... tificial stock market” model or the heterogenous agents model. By using such ...... Rational Asset Price Movements Without News. NBER.

Attitude toward imprecise information - Paris School of Economics
The domain of objects of choice is P × F. The decision maker has a preference relation ... situation is arbitrary and is a mere encoding: hence one can name in the same way two acts that ..... au(1)+(1−a)u(0) and normalize u(1) = 1 and u(0) = 0.

Centre d'Economie de la Sorbonne - Paris School of Economics
regressions on a panel data set to measure the wage gap. They find that ..... The intercept of the African natives could be amazing but this phenomenon.

Attitude toward imprecise information - Paris School of Economics
Page 1 ... maker's attitude to imprecise information: under our axioms, the set of .... To the best of our knowledge, Jaffray [14] is the first to axiomatize a decision ...

Centre d'Economie de la Sorbonne - Paris School of Economics
d'Economie de la Sorbonne, Address: 106-112 bd de l'Hôpital 75647 Paris cedex 13, E- .... regressions on a panel data set to measure the wage gap. They find that ..... tion, gender and housing location (region, size of the city, sensitive urban.

Pareto-efficient tax breaks - Dominik Sachs
Nov 2, 2016 - for education and health (insurance premiums and/or out-of-pocket spending) are also treated favorably by the tax systems of ... by definition not separable from labor-leisure choices. Hence, for .... 2.2 Technology. The output ...

Parental Beliefs and Investment in Children - Andrew Young School of ...
t. The remedial in vestmen t factor includes help with homew ork and tutoring wh ile the activity in vestmen t factor in clu des playing games, reading b o oks, and.

Efficient Repeated Implementation ... - Faculty of Economics
Consider regime ̂R defined in Section 4.2 of LS. ..... Define ¯g = (M,ψ) as the following mechanism: Mi = .... strategy bi except that at (ht,θt) it reports z + 1.

Les Mémos de la Chaire ETA - Paris School of Economics
most of the enforcement power resides with Courts of Law that perform ... but also for setting up auditing mechanisms to force compliance with safety standards.

Les Mémos de la Chaire ETA - Paris School of Economics
of the `regulatory state' is that a new institutional and policy style has emerged, ... for setting up auditing mechanisms to force compliance with safety standards.

paranormal beliefs, religious beliefs and personality ...
Presented in April 2005 at Manchester Metropolitan University, U.K.. This study ... positively correlated with religiosity providing partial support for previous.

Collective Risk-Taking with Threshold Effects - Paris School of ...
Apr 2, 2015 - To the best of our knowledge, this is the first time that this ...... A Appendix: Instructions (for online publication only) ... Once each group member has made his/her decision, the computer randomly determines whether the.

Collective Risk-Taking with Threshold Effects - Paris School of ...
Apr 2, 2015 - 360). The regression in column (4) of Table 6 mirrors column (3) but with the individual. 11The same effect of treatments on payoff is found if we ...

Leverage Stacks and the Financial System - School of Economics ...
Jun 17, 2011 - Is a financial system without netting – where ... than a financial system with netting? ... as security, because she does not know enough to judge ...

Skill Dispersion and Trade Flows - Vancouver School of Economics
database rates industries in three dimensions which are closely associated to .... residual wage dispersion of the effect of firm heterogeneity in order to isolate.

Skill Dispersion and Trade Flows - Vancouver School of Economics
from the International Adult Literacy Survey to show that the effect of skill ...... status and participation in adult education or training programs 12 months prior to ...

School of Business and Economics Universiti Malaysia ...
business activities would affect their decision making in going to the affected ... Network. EC, 2007. Institute for Prospective Technological Studies, Joint ...

Skill Dispersion and Trade Flows - Vancouver School of Economics
communication and interdependence between co'workersnlabor inputs. ..... the company? ...... 38 http://www.bea.gov/industry/xls/1997importPmatrix.xls.

School of Business and Economics Universiti Malaysia ...
Business industries (tourism sectors, airlines, transportations and public facility, local ... fast rising top agenda and most companies adopted corporate social .... Media, advertising, promotions creates social pressure to consume. Climate change i

Facilitators and barriers of parental attitudes and beliefs ...
Mar 18, 2017 - Department of Population Health Sciences, Virginia-Maryland College of Veterinary Medicine, .... Since the 2009 H1N1 influenza pandemic, SLIV programs have ...... ; n.d. [accessed July 3,.

Pareto prinsiippi reflektio.pdf
Whoops! There was a problem loading more pages. Whoops! There was a problem previewing this document. Retrying... Download. Connect more apps.

Stationarity and Regularity of Infinite Collections of Sets
Outline. 1. Finite Collections. Extremal Collection of Sets. Extremal Principle. Stationarity vs Regularity. 2. Infinite Collections. Stationarity vs Regularity. Intersection Rule. Alexander Kruger (University of Ballarat). Stationarity and Regularit

Monopolistic Trades, Accuracy of Beliefs and the ...
∗University of Southern Denmark, Department of Business and Economics, ..... Equi-continuity is a common assumption, and it is not particularly restrictive .... hedging plan when the monopolist has correct beliefs P. Since the monopolist.