Approximation and Characterization of Nash Equilibria of Large Games∗ Guilherme Carmona†

Konrad Podczeck‡

University of Surrey

Universit¨at Wien

March 18, 2012 Abstract We characterize Nash equilibria of games with a continuum of players in terms of approximate equilibria of large finite games. This characterization precisely describes the relationship between equilibrium sets of the two classes of games. In particular, it yields several approximation results for Nash equilibria of games with a continuum of players, which roughly state that all finite-player games that are sufficiently close to a given game with a continuum of players have approximate equilibria that are close to a given Nash equilibrium of the non-atomic game.

Journal of Economic Literature Classification Numbers: C72 Keywords: Nash equilibrium; non-atomic games; large games; approximation.

1

Introduction

Games with a continuum of players are viewed as a tractable idealization of games with a large but finite number of players. This view requires results on the relationship ∗ †

Financial support from Funda¸c˜ao para a Ciˆencia e a Tecnologia is gratefully acknowledged. Address: University of Surrey, Faculty of Business, Economics and Law, School of Economics,

Guildford, GU2 7XH, UK; email: [email protected]. ‡ Address: Institut f¨ ur Wirtschaftswissenschaften, Universit¨at Wien, Hohenstaufengrasse 9, A1010 Wien, Austria. Email: [email protected]

1

between equilibria of games with a continuum of players and of games with a large but finite number of players, in particular to make sure that equilibria of games with a continuum of players are not artifacts of the continuum modeling. Thus, naturally, this topic has been extensively considered in the literature. Amongst the known general results, those of Green (1984), Housman (1988), Khan and Sun (1999) and Al-Najjar (2008) are particularly noteworthy. We have considered this question in a previous paper (Carmona and Podczeck (2009)), where we have shown, among other things, that the existence of equilibrium in games with a continuum of players is equivalent to the existence of approximate equilibria in games with a large finite number of players. In contrast, in this paper, we are interested in the relationship between equilibria of games with a continuum of players and of games with a large but finite number of players per se, i.e., to look at what a Nash equilibrium of general non-atomic games means in terms of approximate equilibria of large finite games. To describe our characterization results informally, for a game with a probability space of players and a strategy profile, let us call the distribution of payoff functions the characteristics distribution, and the joint distribution of payoff functions and actions the characteristics/actions distribution. Our first characterization (formally, the equivalence between conditions 1 and 2 in Theorem 1) says that a strategy profile in a game with a continuum of players is a Nash equilibrium if and only if the corresponding characteristics/actions distribution can be approximated by characteristics/actions distributions of a sequence of finite player games where the number of players increases to infinity and the strategy profiles are asymptotically Nash. Our second characterization (formally, the equivalence between conditions 1 and 3 in Theorem 1) says that, for a game G with a continuum of players, a given strategy profile f is a Nash equilibrium if and only if the following holds: If G0 is any game with a finite but large enough number of players and f 0 is any strategy profile f 0 in G0 such that the characteristics/actions distribution induced by G0 and f 0 is close to that induced by G and f , then f 0 is close to being a Nash equilibrium of G0 .

2

Based on our general characterization result, we also provide approximation results which roughly say that all finite-player games with a characteristics distribution sufficiently close to that of a given game with a continuum of players have approximate equilibria that are close to a given Nash equilibrium of the non-atomic game. We remark that the notion of a strategy profile being close to being a Nash equilibrium can be formalized in two ways: all players choose actions that are close to being optimal responses, or most players choose actions that are close to being optimal responses. We provide approximation results for equilibria in continuum games under both of these formalizations (Theorems 2 – 4). The results with the former formalization (Theorems 3 and 4) require, respectively, an equicontinuity and a compactness assumption on the set of the payoff functions appearing in a given continuum game. Our approximation result with the second formalization (Theorem 2), however, holds without such assumptions. The results of our paper are formulated in the setting of games where players have a common (compact metric) action space and each player’s payoff function depends on his action and on the distribution of actions chosen by all players. This setting provides a sufficiently general framework where our questions can be addressed and our results can be established using (somewhat) elementary arguments. It is likely that these arguments can be extended to obtain more general results, for instance, by allowing the action space to differs across players or by allowing each player’s payoff function to depend on the choice of the others in some more general way.1 We remark that the characterization result provided by (1) ⇔ (3) of Theorem 1 is related to the characterization result for equilibrium distributions of non-atomic games in Lemma 5 of Carmona and Podczeck (2009). However, whereas the latter result applies only to non-atomic games with finite actions and with finitely many characteristics, the characterization result of the present paper holds for general nonatomic games. 1

For example, it would be easy to incorporate the case where players’ payoffs could depend on

the vector of distributions induced by the choices of the players belonging to the each set in a finite partition of the set of players.

3

Two papers that are closely related to ours are Green (1984) and Housman (1988). Both consider the upper hemicontinuity of the Nash equilibrium correspondence and, in particular, obtain limit results for sequences of equilibria of games with a large but finite number of players that converge to any given game with a continuum of players. In contrast, our characterization result is concerned not only with sufficient conditions for a strategy profile to be a Nash equilibrium of a game with a continuum of players, but also with conditions that are, in addition, necessary for this property. Housman (1988) shows, in addition to the above, that in the space of convex games (i.e., games where actions space are convex subsets of some vector space and payoff functions are quasi-concave in the owner’s action), every Nash equilibrium of a game with a continuum of players induces a distribution that, for every game close to the given one, is close to the distribution of an approximate equilibrium of the latter game, provided the payoff functions involved satisfy some equicontinuity condition. The latter result in Housman (1988) thus amounts to some sort of lower hemicontinuity result. Actually, the argument in Housman (1988) does not require convexity assumptions on a non-atomic limit game but it requires convexity assumptions on approximating finite-player games. In contrast, our results do not require such convexity assumptions. In particular, our results apply to setting where there is no linear structure on the action sets. Our work is also related to Al-Najjar (2008), who obtains results connecting approximate equilibria of games with a large finite number of players and equilibria of large games with a countable set of players endowed with a finitely additive distribution. We also mention the work of Khan and Sun (1999) who show, using arguments from non-standard analysis, that the existence of Nash equilibrium for games where the space of players is an atomless Loeb probability space implies the existence of approximate equilibria of games with a large finite number of players. Apart from this, there are no further results concerning the characterization of equilibria in non-atomic games. For literature addressing the relationship between games with a large finite number of players and games with a continuum of players in more specific contexts, see, e.g., 4

the work of Dubey, Mas-Colell, and Shubik (1980) on market games, of Mas-Colell (1983) and Novshek and Sonnenschein (1983) on Cournot competition, and of Allen and Hellwig (1986a) and Allen and Hellwig (1986b) on Bertrand competition.2 We further note that related questions were addressed before in the context of general equilibrium theory (see Hildenbrand (1970), Hildenbrand and Mertens (1972) and Hildenbrand (1974) amongst others). The paper is organized as follows. In Section 2, we introduce our notation and basic definitions. We present our characterizations in Section 3 and our approximation results in Section 4. Some auxiliary results are in the Appendix.

2

Notation and definitions

We consider games where all players have the same action space S and where each player’s payoff depends on his choice and on the distribution of actions induced on S by the choices of all players. The formal setup of the model is as follows. The action space S common to all players is a compact metric space. We let M (S) denote the set of Borel probability measures on S endowed with the narrow topology,3 and C the space of bounded, continuous, real-valued functions on S × M (S) endowed with the sup-norm. Note that since S is a compact metric space, M (S) is compact and metrizable, and hence C is a complete separable metric space. The space of players is described by a probability space (T, Σ, ϕ). A game G is then a triple G = ((T, Σ, ϕ), V, S) where (T, Σ, ϕ) is the probability space of players, S is the action space and V is a measurable function from T to C; V (t) is the payoff function of player t, with the interpretation that V (t)(s, γ) is player t’s payoff when 2

We refer to the survey by Khan and Sun (2002) for a more detailed discussion of the literature

on large games. 3 Recall that if Z is a metric space, the narrow topology on the space M (Z) of Borel probability R measures γ on Z is the coarsest topology on M (Z) making the map γ 7→ f dγ continuous for every bounded continuous real-valued function f on Z; if Z is a compact metric space, then M (Z) is compact and metrizable for the narrow topology.

5

he plays action s and faces a distribution γ in M (S) induced by the actions of all players. We will consider only games G = ((T, Σ, ϕ), V, S) where either (T, Σ, ϕ) is atomless and complete, or T is finite, Σ = 2T and ϕ is the uniform distribution on T (i.e., ϕ({t}) = 1/|T | for all t ∈ T ). The former case will be referred to as a non-atomic game, and the latter as a finite-player game. By a strategy profile f in a game G = ((T, Σ, ϕ), V, S) we mean a measurable function f : T → S. Measurability of a strategy profile f ensures that the distribution of f is defined in M (S), so that f can be evaluated by players’ payoff functions. Of course, measurability does not impose any restriction on strategy profiles if G is a game with finitely many players. Note that, in any case, if f : T → S is measurable, then so is any function f 0 : T → S which differs from f in only one point of S, so the notion of strategy profile we employ captures individual deviations from any given strategy profile. In the sequel, given any game G = ((T, Σ, ϕ), V, S) and any strategy profile f in G, the distribution of f is denoted by ϕ ◦ f −1 , and player t’s payoff by U (t)(f ) = V (t)(f (t), ϕ ◦ f −1 ).

(1)

Further, f \ t s denotes the strategy profile obtained if player t changes his choice from f (t) to s. Thus, f \ t s is the strategy profile defined by setting f \ t s(t) = s, and f\t s(t0 ) = f (t0 ) for all t0 6= t. Note that if G is non-atomic, then ϕ ◦ (f\t s)−1 = ϕ ◦ f −1 , i.e., in a non-atomic game no player has any impact on the distributions of actions. For all ε ≥ 0, the set {t ∈ T : U (t)(f ) ≥ sups∈S U (t)(f \ t s) − ε} is measurable. Indeed, this is clear for a game with finitely many players. If the space (T, Σ, ϕ) of players is non-atomic then, by the previous paragraph, this set is just (V, f )−1 ({(u, y) ∈ C × S : u(y, ϕ ◦ f −1 ) ≥ u(x, ϕ ◦ f −1 ) − ε for all x ∈ S}) and therefore measurable because {(u, y) ∈ C×S : u(y, ϕ◦f −1 ) ≥ u(x, ϕ◦f −1 )−ε for all x ∈ S} is closed in C × S and (V, f ) is (jointly) measurable.4 4

The joint measurability of (V, f ) holds because S and C are separable metric spaces; see, e.g.

Fremlin (2003, Proposition 418B, p. 111).

6

For all real numbers ε, η ≥ 0, we say that a strategy profile f is an (ε, η)-equilibrium of the game G = ((T, Σ, ϕ), V, S) if µ ¶ ϕ {t ∈ T : U (t)(f ) ≥ sup U (t)(f \ t s) − ε} ≥ 1 − η.

(2)

s∈S

Thus, in an (ε, η)-equilibrium, only a fraction of players smaller than η can gain more than ε by deviating from f . A strategy profile f is an ε-equilibrium of G if it is an (ε, η)-equilibrium for η = 0. Finally, a strategy profile f is a Nash equilibrium of G if it is an ε-equilibrium of G for ε = 0. If G = ((T, Σ, ϕ), V, S) is a game and f a strategy profile in G, ϕ◦(V, f )−1 denotes the (joint) distribution of the function (V, f ), i.e. the Borel probability measure on C × S defined by setting ϕ ◦ (V, f )−1 (B) = ϕ((V, f )−1 (B)) for every Borel set B in C ×S. As noted in footnote 4, (V, f ) is jointly measurable since C and S are separable metric spaces, and so ϕ ◦ (V, f )−1 is well-defined. Convergence in M (C × S) is always understood with respect to the narrow topology on M (C × S), writing M (C × S) for the space of all Borel measures on C × S. Let ρ denote the Prohorov metric on M (C × S) and note that it induces the narrow topology. We abuse notation by also using ρ to denote the Prohorov metric on M (C) and on M (S). Let X be a metric space. The Borel σ-algebra of X is denoted by B(X). For all x ∈ X, 1x denotes the Dirac measure at x, i.e., 1x (B) = 1 if x ∈ B and 1x (B) = 0 if x 6∈ B, for all B ∈ B(X). If Y is a metric space and τ ∈ M (X × Y ), τX (resp. τY ) denotes the marginal distribution of τ on X (resp. Y ).

3

Characterization of Nash equilibria of non-atomic games

The main result of this section states two characterizations of Nash equilibria of non-atomic games in terms of (ε, η)-equilibria of games with finitely many players. One characterizations shows that a strategy profile in a non-atomic game is a Nash equilibrium if and only if the corresponding characteristics/actions distribution can be approximated by the characteristics/actions distributions of a games with 7

finitely many players and approximate equilibria in these games with the level of approximation being as small as desired if the number of players is sufficiently large. This the content of (1) ⇔ (2) in Theorem 1 below. The second characterization, which is (1) ⇔ (3) in that theorem, says that, given a non-atomic game G, a strategy profile f is a Nash equilibrium in G if and only if for any finite-player game G0 and any strategy profile f 0 in G0 such that the characteristics/actions distribution induced by G0 and f 0 is close that induced by G and f , it is true that f 0 is an approximate equilibrium of G0 , where the level of approximation is as small as desired provided that the number of players in G0 is sufficiently large. The first of these two characterizations may be seen as a limit result for approximate equilibria of large finite-player games whereas the second may be seem as a result on asymptotic implementation of equilibria of games with a continuum of players. Theorem 1 Let G = ((T, Σ, ϕ), V, S) be a non-atomic game, and f a strategy profile in G. Then the following are equivalent. 1. f is a Nash equilibrium of G. 2. There are sequences {Gn }n , {fn }n and {εn }n , where Gn = ((Tn , Σn , ϕn ), Vn , S) is a finite-player game and fn is an (εn , εn )-equilibrium of Gn for each n ∈ N, such that |Tn | → ∞, ϕn ◦ (Vn , fn )−1 → ϕ ◦ (V, f )−1 and εn → 0. 3. If {Gn }n and {fn }n are sequences, where Gn = ((Tn , Σn , ϕn ), Vn , S) is a finiteplayer game and fn is a strategy profile of Gn for each n ∈ N, such that |Tn | → ∞ and ϕn ◦ (Vn , fn )−1 → ϕ ◦ (V, f )−1 , then there is a sequence {εn }n in R+ such that εn → 0 and fn is an (εn , εn )-equilibrium of Gn for all sufficiently large n. Before we state the proof, we remark that (2) ⇒ (1) of this theorem is already contained in Lemma 11 of Carmona and Podczeck (2009). This latter paper also contains a result that is analogous to (1) ⇒ (3) but covers only the special case of finite action spaces and players’ characteristics belonging to a finite set. Because of this, the argument in the proof of this latter result does not apply to the more general setting treated in Theorem 1. 8

Proof of Theorem 1. (1) ⇒ (3) For all n ∈ N, let εn ∈ R+ ∪ {∞} be defined by εn = inf{ε ≥ 0 : ϕn ({t ∈ Tn : Un (t)(fn ) ≥ sup Un (t)(fn \ t s) − ε}) ≥ 1 − ε}. s∈S

We need to show that limn εn = 0. Set γ = ϕ ◦ f −1 , and for each n ∈ N, set γn = ϕ ◦ fn−1 . By hypothesis, γn → γ. For each n ∈ N, let Bn = {γ 0 ∈ M (S) : ρ(γn , γ 0 ) ≤ 1/|Tn |}. Then for each n ∈ N, Bn is compact and for each t ∈ Tn and s ∈ S, we have ϕ ◦ (fn \ t s)−1 ∈ Bn , by definition of the Prohorov metric. Note also that since |Tn | → ∞, we have γn0 → γ whenever {γn0 }n is a sequence with γn0 ∈ Bn for each n ∈ N. Since S and the sets Bn are compact, we can define continuous functions h and hn from C × S to R+ by setting h(u, x) = max{u(y, γ) : y ∈ S} − u(x, γ) and hn (u, x) = max{u(y, γ 0 ) : y ∈ S, γ 0 ∈ Bn } − u(x, γn ). Using the compactness of S and the fact that γn0 → γ whenever γn0 ∈ Bn for each n ∈ N, it is straightforward to check that hn → h uniformly on compact subsets of C × S. Set τ = ϕ ◦ (V, f )−1 , and for each n ∈ N, set τn = ϕn ◦ (Vn , fn )−1 . Since f is a Nash equilibrium of the non-atomic game G, we have τ ({(u, s) ∈ C × S : h((u, s)) 6= 0}) = ϕ({t ∈ T : h ◦ (V, f )(t) 6= 0}) = 0.

(3)

On the other hand, note that for each n ∈ N and each t ∈ Tn , we have sup Un (t)(fn \ t s) = sup Vn (t)(s, ϕn ◦ (fn \ t s)−1 ) ≤ s∈S

s∈S

Vn (t)(s, γ 0 )

sup s∈S,γ 0 ∈B

n

because ϕ ◦ fn \ t s ∈ Bn for each s ∈ S. Consequently, given ε > 0, for each n ∈ N we have ¡ ¢ ϕn {t ∈ Tn : Un (t)(fn ) ≤ sup Un (t)(fn \ t s) − ε} ¡

s∈S

≤ ϕn {t ∈ Tn : Vn (t)(fn (t), γn ) ≤ ¡

sup s∈S,γ 0 ∈Bn

¢ = ϕn {t ∈ Tn : hn ◦ (Vn , fn )(t) ≥ ε} ¢ = τn ({(u, s) ∈ C × S : hn (u, s) ≥ ε} .

9

Vn (t)(s, γ) − ε}

¢ (4)

Since τn → τ by hypothesis, since h and, for all n ∈ N, hn are continuous, and since −1 hn → h uniformly on compact subsets of C × S, we must have τn ◦ h−1 by n → τ ◦h

Hildenbrand (1974, p. 51, 38). In particular, we have that −1 lim τn ◦ h−1 n ({r ∈ R+ : r ≥ ε}) ≤ τ ◦ h ({r ∈ R+ : r ≥ ε}),

whence lim τn ({(u, s) ∈ C × S : hn (u, s) ≥ ε}) ≤ τ ({(u, s) ∈ C × S : h(u, s) ≥ ε}). ¡ ¢ Hence, by (3) and (4), ϕn {t ∈ Tn : Un (t)(fn ) ≤ sups∈S Un (t)(fn \ t s) − ε} < ε for all n sufficiently large. This implies that εn ≤ ε and, since ε is arbitrary, that limn εn = 0. (3) ⇒ (2) Recall the standard fact that if G is a non-atomic game and f a strategy profile in G, then a sequence {Gn }n = {((Tn , Σn , ϕn ), Vn , S)}n of finiteplayer games together with a sequence {fn }n of strategy profiles for the Gn ’s such that ϕn ◦ (Vn , fn )−1 → ϕ ◦ (V, f )−1 and |Tn | → ∞ do exist.5 In view of this fact, it is clear that (3) implies (2). (2) ⇒ (1) This follows from Lemma 11 in Carmona and Podczeck (2009) by setting ε = 0 and ηn = εn for all n. For sake of completeness, we give the argument here. Set τ = ϕ ◦ (V, f )−1 and γ = ϕ ◦ f −1 . It suffices to show that whenever (u, x) ∈ supp(τ ), then u(x, γ) = maxy∈S u(y, γ). To this end, for each n ∈ N, set τn = ϕn ◦ (Vn , fn )−1 and γn = ϕ ◦ fn−1 . Let Sn ⊆ Tn be given as Sn = {t ∈ Tn : Un (t)(fn ) < sups∈S Un (t)(fn \ t s) − εn }. Set An = (Vn , fn )(Sn ) and note that τn (An ) = ϕn (Sn ) for each n ∈ N. Thus τn (An ) → 0 by hypothesis. Consider any (u, x) ∈ supp(τ ). Since τn → τ by hypothesis, by Lemma 12 in Carmona and Podczeck (2009), we may find a subsequence {τnk }k of {τn }n and, for each k ∈ N, a point (uk , xk ) ∈ supp(τnk )\Ank so that (uk , xk ) → (u, x). In particular, then, for each k ∈ N, (uk , xk ) = (Vnk , fnk )(tk ) for some tk ∈ Tnk \Snk . Pick any y ∈ S and, for each k ∈ N, let γk0 = ϕnk ◦ (fnk \ tk y)−1 . Then for each k ∈ N we must have 5

This fact is a straightforward consequence of the fact that if τ is a Borel probability measure

on separable metric space Z, there is an equidistributed sequence in Z for τ , i.e. a sequence {zi }i of Pn points of Z such that limn→∞ n1 i=1 1zi = τ .

10

uk (xk , γnk ) ≥ uk (y, γk0 ) − εnk because tk ∈ Tnk \Snk . Note also that γnk → γ and hence, since 1/|Tn | → 0, γk0 → γ as well. Since εnk → 0 by the hypotheses of the lemma, it follows that u(x, γ) ≥ u(y, γ). As y ∈ S was chosen arbitrarily, we may conclude that u(x, γ) = maxy∈S u(y, γ).

4

Approximation of Nash equilibria of non-atomic games

In this section, we present several approximation results for Nash equilibria of games with a continuum of players. The motivation for these results arises from the characterization of Nash equilibria of non-atomic games presented in Theorem 1, which can roughly be described as establishing the approximate continuity of the equilibrium correspondence in the following sense. The equilibrium correspondence maps games, represented by their distribution over payoff functions and number of players, to the distributions over payoffs and actions induced by the game and its Nash equilibria. As shown in Green (1984) and Housman (1988) (see also (2) ⇒ (1) in Theorem 1 above), the equilibrium correspondence is upper hemicontinuous for some appropriate topologies. Here, we focus on properties that correspond to the lower hemicontinuity of the equilibrium correspondence. The properties we focus on here require, in particular, all finite-player games, with a sufficiently large number of players and a distribution over payoff functions sufficiently close to the one of the given non-atomic game, to have a Nash equilibrium such that the distribution induced by it and by the players’ payoff function is close to the one induced by the given Nash equilibrium of the non-atomic game. Although this property does not hold in general, Theorem 2 shows that it holds for (ε, ε)-equilibria in general games. Furthermore, Theorems 3 to 4 show that it also holds for ε-equilibrium when special assumptions, such as compactness and equicontinuity, are added. Theorem 2 Let G = ((T, Σ, ϕ), V, S) be a non-atomic game, and f a Nash equilibrium of G. Then, for all η, ε > 0, there is δ > 0 such that if G0 = ((T 0 , Σ0 , ϕ0 ), V 0 , S) 11

is a finite-player game satisfying ρ(ϕ0 ◦ (V 0 )−1 , ϕ ◦ V −1 ) < δ and 1/|T 0 | < δ, there exists an (ε, ε)-equilibrium f 0 of G0 such that ρ(ϕ0 ◦ (V 0 , f 0 )−1 , ϕ ◦ (V, f )−1 ) < η. Proof. Fix η, ε > 0. By (1) ⇒ (3) in Theorem 1 there is a number δ1 > 0 such that if G0 = ((T 0 , Σ0 , ϕ0 ), V 0 , S) is a finite-player game satisfying 1/|T 0 | < δ1 and f 0 is a strategy profile of G0 with ρ(ϕ0 ◦ (V 0 , f 0 )−1 , ϕ ◦ (V, f )−1 ) < δ1 , then f 0 is an (ε, ε)equilibrium of G0 . By Lemma 4 in the Appendix, there is a number δ2 > 0 such that if G0 = ((T 0 , Σ0 , ϕ0 ), V 0 , S) is a finite-player game satisfying ρ(ϕ0 ◦ (V 0 )−1 , ϕ ◦ V −1 ) < δ2 and 1/|T 0 | < δ2 , there is a strategy profile f 0 for G0 such that ρ(ϕ0 ◦ (V 0 , f 0 )−1 , ϕ ◦ (V, f )−1 ) < min{η, δ 1 }. Then, δ = min{δ1 , δ2 } is a number as desired. In the following results, we consider the case of non-atomic and finite-player games whose players’ payoff functions belong to a given equicontinuous set of payoff functions. As Theorem 3 below shows, this allow us to strengthen the conclusion of Theorem 2 from (ε, ε)-equilibrium to ε-equilibrium. The assumption of equicontinuous payoff functions allows us to change the actions of those players who are not ε-optimizing in the (ε, ε)-equilibrium obtained via Theorem 2. In fact, since the fraction of these players is small, such change has a small impact on the distribution of actions, and due to equicontinuity, on players’ payoffs. In the statement of Theorem 3 and in its proof, given a subset K of C, Bδ (K) denotes the set {u ∈ C : inf v∈K ||u − v|| < δ} (where || · || means the sup-norm on C). Theorem 3 Let K ⊆ C be equicontinuous, G = ((T, Σ, ϕ), V, S) a non-atomic game with V (T ) ⊆ K, and f a Nash equilibrium of G. Then, for all η, ε > 0, there is δ > 0 such that for all finite-player games G0 = ((T 0 , Σ0 , ϕ0 ), V 0 , S) satisfying V 0 (T 0 ) ⊆ Bδ (K), ρ(ϕ0 ◦ (V 0 )−1 , ϕ ◦ V −1 ) < δ and 1/|T 0 | < δ, there exists an ε-equilibrium f 0 of G0 such that ρ(ϕ0 ◦ (V 0 , f 0 )−1 , ϕ ◦ (V, f )−1 ) < η. Proof. Fix η, ε > 0. By the equicontinuity of K, we can choose a number θ > 0 such that |v(s, τ ) − v(s0 , τ 0 )| < ε/4 whenever v ∈ K, d(s, s0 ) ≤ θ for s, s0 ∈ S and ρ(τ, τ 0 ) ≤ θ for τ, τ 0 ∈ M (S). Clearly, we can choose θ so as to have in addition θ < min{ε/4, η/2}. 12

By Theorem 2, there is a 0 < δ < min{θ, 8ε} such that if G0 = ((T 0 , Σ0 , ϕ0 ), V 0 , S) is a finite-player game satisfying ρ(ϕ0 ◦ (V 0 )−1 , ϕ ◦ V −1 ) < δ and 1/|T 0 | < δ then G0 has an (θ, θ)-equilibrium fˆ satisfying ρ(ϕ0 ◦ (V 0 , fˆ)−1 , ϕ ◦ (V, f )−1 ) < θ. Given such a game V 0 and (θ, θ)-equilibrium fˆ of G0 , suppose V 0 (T 0 ) ⊆ Bδ (K) and define a strategy profile f 0 in G0 by letting f 0 (t) be a solution to maxs∈S V 0 (t)(s, ϕ0 ◦ fˆ−1 ) in case V 0 (t)(fˆ(t), ϕ0 ◦ fˆ−1 ) < sups∈S V 0 (t)(s, ϕ0 ◦ (fˆ\ t s)−1 ) − θ, and f 0 (t) = fˆ(t) otherwise. As fˆ is an (θ, θ)-equilibrium of G0 , the fraction of players t in G0 for which fˆ(t) is not within θ of a best reply to ϕ0 ◦fˆ−1 is smaller than θ. Thus the fraction of players t in G0 for which fˆ(t) differs from f 0 (t) is smaller than θ. This implies ρ(ϕ0 ◦f 0−1 , ϕ0 ◦ fˆ−1 ) ≤ θ and that ρ(ϕ0 ◦ (f 0 \t s)−1 , ϕ0 ◦ (fˆ\t s)−1 ) ≤ θ for all t ∈ T 0 and s ∈ S. Note also that ˆ t s)−1 ) < θ since 1/|T 0 | < θ. These facts, together with the fact that ρ(ϕ0 ◦ fˆ−1 , ϕ0 ◦ (f\ V 0 (T 0 ) ⊆ Bδ (K), imply that f 0 is an ε-equilibrium as follows. Let t ∈ T 0 and v ∈ K be such that ||v − V 0 (t)|| < δ. If t ∈ T 0 is such that V 0 (t)(fˆ(t), ϕ0 ◦ fˆ−1 ) < sups∈S V (t)(s, ϕ0 ◦ (fˆ\ t s)−1 ) − θ, then for all s ∈ S, V 0 (t)(f 0 (t), ϕ0 ◦ f 0−1 ) > v(f 0 (t), ϕ0 ◦ f 0−1 ) − δ ε ε > v(f 0 (t), ϕ0 ◦ fˆ−1 ) − δ − > V 0 (t)(f 0 (t), ϕ0 ◦ fˆ−1 ) − 2δ − 4 4 ε ε 0 0 −1 0 −1 ˆ ˆ ≥ V (t)(s, ϕ ◦ f ) − 2δ − > v(s, ϕ ◦ f ) − 3δ − 4 4 ε 3ε > v(s, ϕ0 ◦ (fˆ\ t s)−1 ) − 3δ − > v(s, ϕ0 ◦ (f 0 \ t s)−1 ) − 3δ − 2 4 3ε > V 0 (t)(s, ϕ0 ◦ (f 0 \ t s)−1 ) − 4δ − > V 0 (t)(s, ϕ0 ◦ (f 0 \ t s)−1 ) − ε. 4 Otherwise, i.e., if V 0 (t)(fˆ(t), ϕ0 ◦ fˆ−1 ) ≥ sups∈S V 0 (t)(s, ϕ0 ◦ (fˆ\t s)−1 ) − θ, then for all s ∈ S we have that f 0 (t) = fˆ(t) and V 0 (t)(f 0 (t), ϕ0 ◦ f 0−1 ) > v(f 0 (t), ϕ0 ◦ f 0−1 ) − δ ε ε > v(f 0 (t), ϕ0 ◦ fˆ−1 ) − δ − > V 0 (t)(f 0 (t), ϕ0 ◦ fˆ−1 ) − 2δ − 4 4 ε ε 0 −1 0 0 −1 ˆ ˆ > V (t)(s, ϕ ◦ (f \ t s) ) − 2δ − − θ > v(s, ϕ ◦ (f \ t s) ) − 3δ − − θ 4 4 ε ε 0 0 −1 0 0 0 −1 > v(s, ϕ ◦ (f \ t s) ) − 3δ − − θ > V (t)(s, ϕ ◦ (f \ t s) ) − 4δ − − θ 2 2 0 0 0 −1 > V (t)(s, ϕ ◦ (f \ t s) ) − ε. 13

Finally, note that ρ(ϕ0 ◦ (V 0 , fˆ)−1 , ϕ0 ◦ (V 0 , f 0 )−1 ) ≤ θ and so ρ(ϕ0 ◦ (V 0 , f 0 )−1 , ϕ ◦ (V, f )−1 ) < 2θ = η. Theorem 4 below improves over Theorem 3 by providing an uniformity over the non-atomic games with V (T ) ⊆ K and its Nash equilibria. This is achieved by assuming that players’ payoff functions are contained in a set in C which is not only equicontinuous but also bounded. Theorem 4 Let K be a compact subset of C. Then, for all ε > 0, there is a δ > 0 such that if G = ((T, Σ, ϕ), V, S) is a non-atomic game with V (T ) ⊆ K, and f a Nash equilibrium of G, then every finite-player game G0 = ((T 0 , Σ0 , ϕ0 ), V 0 , S) satisfying V 0 (T 0 ) ⊆ Bδ (K), 1/|T 0 | < δ and ρ(ϕ0 ◦ (V 0 )−1 , ϕ ◦ V −1 ) < δ has an ε-equilibrium f 0 such that ρ(ϕ0 ◦ (V 0 , f 0 )−1 , ϕ ◦ (V, f )−1 ) < ε. Proof. Let © Z = τ ∈ M (K × S) : there is a non-atomic game G = ((T, Σ, ϕ), V, S) ª with V (T ) ⊆ K and a Nash equilibrium f of G such that τ = ϕ ◦ (V, f )−1 . Using the fact that every τ ∈ M (K × S) can be represented as τ = ϕ ◦ (V, f )−1 for some mapping (V, f ) from an atomless probability space (T, Σ, ϕ) to K ×S, arguments analogous to that in the proof of (2) ⇒ (1) in Theorem 1 show that Z is closed in M (K × S), hence compact because compactness of K × S implies that M (K × S) is compact. Fix ε > 0. Noting that K, being compact, is equicontinuous by the Ascoli-Arzela Theorem, for each τ = ϕ ◦ (V, f )−1 ∈ Z choose a number δτ > 0 corresponding to G = ((T, Σ, ϕ), V, S), f , ε and η = ε/2 according to Theorem 3, and then let Uτ = {τ 0 ∈ Z : ρ(τK0 , τK ) < δτ /2, ρ(τ 0 , τ ) < ε/2)}. Then, for each τ ∈ Z, Uτ is an open neighborhood of τ in Z, and by the choice of δτ and the triangle inequality it is ˆ = ((Tˆ, Σ, ˆ ϕ), plain that if G ˆ Vˆ , S) is a finite-player game satisfying Vˆ (Tˆ) ⊆ Bδτ (K), ρ(ϕˆ ◦ Vˆ −1 , τK0 ) < δτ /2 for some τ 0 ∈ Uτ and 1/|Tˆ| < δτ , there is an ε-equilibrium fˆ of ˆ such that ρ(ϕˆ ◦ (Vˆ , fˆ)−1 , τ 0 ) < ε. G Being compact, Z can be covered by finitely many of the sets Uτ , say Uτ1 , . . . Uτn , and setting δ = min{δτi /2 : i = 1, . . . , n}, we have a δ > 0 as desired. 14

A

Appendix

In this appendix, we collect the lemmas that are used in the proof of our main results. As before, convergence of measures on metric spaces is always understood with respect to the narrow topology. For finite sets, the consequences of convergence of probability measures are easy to understand because it implies that the probability of each point in the set converges to the corresponding limit probability. This property does not hold for general separable metric spaces. However, Lemma 1 shows that, for every probability measure, the space can be partitioned into a countable collection of measurable subsets with a small diameter such that the probabilities of those sets converge to the corresponding limit probability. Lemma 1 Let X be a separable metric space, and µ a Borel probability measure on X. Then given any ε > 0 there is a countable partition (Ei )i∈N of X into Borel sets, each with diameter less than ε, such that whenever {µn }n is sequence in M (X) with µn → µ, then µn (Ei ) → µ(Ei ) for each i ∈ N. Proof. Recall the following facts, denoting by ∂A the boundary of a subset A of a topological space Z. (a) If Z is a metric space, and µ a probability measure on Z, then the set of open sets O with µ(∂O) = 0 is a base for the topology of Z; see Fremlin (2003, 411G(i)). (b) If Z is a metric space and T is any base for the topology of Z, then give ε > 0 there is a set T 0 ⊆ T such that each element of T 0 has diameter less than ε and T 0 is still a base. (To see this, let O be an open subset of Z and x ∈ O. There is a real number r > 0 with 0 < r < ε/2 such that Br (x) ⊆ O where Br (x) is the open r-ball around x. As T is a base, there is V ∈ T such that x ∈ V ⊆ Br (x), and such set V must have diameter less than ε.) (c) If Z is any topological space and A and B are subsets of Z, then ∂(B\A) ⊆ ∂B ∪ S S ∂A; if A0 , . . . , An are finitely many subsets of Z, then ∂( ni=0 Ai ) ⊆ ni=0 ∂Ai . 15

Let µ be a Borel probability measure on X and fix ε > 0. Since X is second countable, using (a) and (b) it follows that there is a countable family (Bi )i∈N of S open subsets of X with ∞ i=0 Bi = X such that, for each i ∈ N, the diameter of Bi is less than ε and µ(∂Bi ) = 0. Define a family (Ei )i∈N of Borel sets of X by setting S Ei = Bi \ i−1 j=0 Bj for each i ∈ N. Use (c) and the fact that the union of finitely many null sets is a null set to see that µ(∂Ei ) = 0 for each i ∈ N. Hence, the conclusion follows from the Portmanteau Theorem. Lemma 2 considers a sequence of functions converging in distribution and shows that both the limit function and the ones in the sequence can be closely approximated by functions having a finite range. By finite probability space we mean a probability space (T, Σ, ϕ) where T is finite, Σ = 2T , and ϕ is the uniform distribution. Lemma 2 Let (X, dX ) be a separable metric space, (T, Σ, ϕ) a probability space, and g : T → X a measurable mapping. Furthermore, let {(Tn , Σn , ϕn )}n∈N be a sequence of finite probability spaces together with mappings gn : Tn → X, n ∈ N, such that ϕn ◦ gn−1 → ϕ ◦ g −1 . Then, for all ε > 0, there are a finite set F ⊆ X and mappings g¯ : T → F and g¯n : Tn → F , for all n ∈ N, such that ϕn ◦ g¯n−1 → ϕ ◦ g¯−1 , ϕ({t ∈ T : dX (¯ g (t), g(t)) ≤ ε}) > 1 − ε, and ϕn ({t ∈ Tn : dX (¯ gn (t), gn (t)) ≤ ε}) > 1 − ε for all sufficiently large n. Proof. Fix ε > 0 and let (Ei )i∈N be a partition of X chosen with respect to ϕ◦g −1 S and ε according to Lemma 1. We can find an ¯i such that ϕ ◦ g −1 ( i≥¯i Ei )) < ε. For each i ≤ ¯i, pick a point xi ∈ Ei and let F = {xi : 1 ≤ i ≤ ¯i}. Define g¯ : T → F by setting g¯(t) = xi if g(t) ∈ Ei for i < ¯i and g¯(t) = x¯i if S g(t) ∈ i≥¯i Ei . Analogously, for each n ∈ N, define g¯n : Tn → F by setting g¯n (t) = xi S if gn (t) ∈ Ei for i < ¯i, and g¯n (t) = x¯i if gn (t) ∈ i≥¯i Ei . S¯ S¯i−1 −1 By choice of (Ei )i∈N , we have ϕn ◦ gn−1 ( i−1 i=0 Ei ) → ϕ ◦ g ( i=0 Ei ) and hence S S S ϕn ◦ gn−1 ( i≥¯i Ei ) → ϕ ◦ g −1 ( i≥¯i Ei ). Consequently ϕn ◦ gn−1 ( i≥¯i Ei ) < ε for all 16

sufficiently large n, whence, since the diameter of Ei is at most ε by choice of (Ei )i∈N , we have ϕn ({t ∈ Tn : dX (¯ gn (t), gn (t)) ≤ ε}) > 1 − ε for all sufficiently large n. Similarly, we have ϕ({t ∈ T : dX (¯ g (t), g(t)) ≤ ε}) > 1 − ε. Finally note that we have ϕn ◦ g¯n−1 ({xi }) = ϕn ◦ gn−1 (Ei ) → ϕ ◦ g −1 (Ei ) = ϕ ◦ g¯−1 ({xi }) for each 1 ≤ i < ¯i, and therefore also ϕn ◦ g¯n−1 ({x¯i }) → ϕ¯ ◦ g −1 ({x¯i }). Thus, since ϕ◦ g¯−1 and all the measures ϕn ◦ g¯n−1 have a support in the same finite set {x1 , . . . , x¯i }, we have ϕn ◦ g¯n−1 → ϕ ◦ g¯−1 . Lemma 4 considers a lower hemicontinuity property of the correspondence that assigns to each game its set of strategy profiles. This property is analogous to the one considered in our approximation results, in the sense that it is only established for non-atomic games and only finite-player games are considered as approximations. Lemma 3 is used in its proof and, although stated abstractly, it considers a special case of Lemma 4, namely that of non-atomic games with finitely many actions and payoff functions. Lemma 3 Let X and Y be finite sets, and τ a probability measure on X × Y . If {(Tn , Σn , ϕn )}n∈N is a sequence of finite probability spaces with |Tn | → ∞, and for each n ∈ N, gn : Tn → X is such that ϕn ◦ gn−1 → τX , then there is a mapping fn : Tn → Y for each n ∈ N such that ϕn ◦ (gn , fn )−1 → τ . Proof. Let X = {x1 , . . . , xk } and Y = {y1 , . . . , ym }. For each 1 ≤ i ≤ k, 1 ≤ j ≤ m, and n ∈ N, let µi = τX ({xi }), τi,j = τ ({(xi , yj )}), and Tin = {t ∈ Tn : gn (t) = xi }. P Note that for each 1 ≤ i ≤ k, |Tin |/|Tn | → µi by hypothesis and that m j=1 τi,j = µi . n = Making the convention 0/0 = 0, for each 1 ≤ i ≤ k and n ∈ N, define θi,j P n n = |Tin | − m−1 max{θ ∈ N : θ ≤ |Tin |τi,j /µi } for 1 ≤ j ≤ m − 1, and θi,m j=1 θi,j . We can

then choose a mapping fn : Tn → Y for each n ∈ N such that ¯ ¯ n ¯{t ∈ Tn : (gn (t), fn (t)) = (xi , yj )}¯ = θi,j 17

for all 1 ≤ i ≤ k and 1 ≤ j ≤ m. Note that for each 0 ≤ i ≤ k and 1 ≤ j ≤ m − 1, n θi,j |Tin |τi,j 1 |T n |τi,j − < ≤ i |Tn |µi |Tn | |Tn | |Tn |µi n (again, 0/0 = 0), showing that θi,j /|Tn | → τi,j for such i and j because |Tin |/|Tn | → µi P n and 1/|Tn | → 0. Consequently, we also have θi,m /|Tn | → µi − m−1 j=1 τi,j = τi,m for

each 1 ≤ i ≤ k. It is now plain that ϕn ◦ (gn , fn )−1 → τ . Lemma 4 Let G = ((T, Σ, ϕ), V, S) be a non-atomic game, and f a strategy profile in G. Then for each ε > 0 there exists δ > 0 such that for all finite-player games G0 = ((T 0 , Σ0 , ϕ0 ), V 0 , S) satisfying ρ(ϕ0 ◦ (V 0 )−1 , ϕ ◦ V −1 ) < δ and 1/|T 0 | < δ there exists a strategy profile f 0 in G0 such that ρ(ϕ0 ◦ (V 0 , f 0 )−1 , ϕ ◦ (V, f )−1 ) < ε. Proof. It suffices to show that, given ε > 0, if {Gn }n = {((Tn , Σn , ϕn ), Vn , S)}n is any sequence of games with finitely many players satisfying both |Tn | → ∞ and ϕn ◦ Vn−1 → ϕ ◦ V −1 , then for all sufficiently large n there are strategy profiles fn : Tn → S such that ρ(ϕn ◦ (Vn , fn )−1 , ϕ ◦ (V, f )−1 ) < ε. Fix ε > 0 and let {Gn }n be a sequence of games with finitely many players satisfying the above requirements. By Lemma 2, there are a finite set F ⊆ C and measurable mappings V¯ : T → F and V¯n : Tn → F , for all n ∈ N, such that the following hold (a) ϕn ◦ V¯n−1 → ϕ ◦ V¯ , (b) ϕ({t ∈ T : ||V¯ (t) − V (t)|| ≤ ε/4}) > 1 − ε/4, and (c) for all sufficiently large n, ϕn ({t ∈ Tn : ||V¯n (t) − Vn (t)|| ≤ ε/4}) > 1 − ε/4. Since S is compact, we can choose a finite partition {Bl }m l=1 of S into Borel sets, each with diameter less than or equal to ε/4. For each 1 ≤ l ≤ m pick a point sl ∈ Bl . Set Y = {s1 , . . . , sm } and let f¯ : T → Y be defined by f¯(t) = sl if f (t) ∈ Bl . Then, from (b) above, ρ(ϕ ◦ (V, f )−1 , ϕ ◦ (V¯ , f¯)−1 ) ≤ ε/4 (for an appropriate product metric on C × S). As F and Y are finite, by (a) we can use Lemma 3 to find mappings fn : Tn → Y , n ∈ N, such that ϕn ◦(V¯n , fn )−1 → ϕ◦(V¯ , f¯)−1 , and so ρ(ϕ◦(V¯ , f¯)−1 , ϕn ◦(V¯n , fn )−1 ) < ε/4 for all sufficiently large n. Note that from (c) we must have ρ(ϕn ◦ (V¯n , fn )−1 , ϕn ◦ (Vn , fn )−1 ) ≤ ε/4 for all sufficiently large n. Using the triangle inequality, it follows that ρ(ϕ ◦ (V, f )−1 , ϕn ◦ (Vn , fn )−1 ) < ε for all sufficiently large n, as was to be shown.

18

References Al-Najjar, N. (2008): “Large Games and the Law of Large Numbers,” Games and Economic Behavior, 64, 1–34. Allen, B., and M. Hellwig (1986a): “Bertrand-Edgeworth Oligopoly in Large Markets,” Review of Economic Studies, 53, 175–204. (1986b): “Price-Setting Firms and the Oligopolistic Foundations of Perfect Competition,” American Economic Review, 76, 387–392. Carmona, G., and K. Podczeck (2009): “On the Existence of Pure Strategy Nash Equilibria in Large Games,” Journal of Economic Theory, 144, 1300–1319. Dubey, P., A. Mas-Colell, and M. Shubik (1980): “Efficiency Properties of Strategic Market Games: An Axiomatic Approach,” Journal of Economic Theory, 22, 339–362. Fremlin, D. (2003): Measure Theory, vol. 4: Topological Measure Spaces. Torres Fremlin, Colchester. Green, E. (1984): “Continuum and Finite-Player Noncooperative Models of Competition,” Econometrica, 52, 975–993. Hildenbrand, W. (1970): “On Economies with Many Agents,” Journal of Economic Theory, 2, 161–188. (1974): Core and Equilibria of a Large Economy. Princeton University Press, Princeton. Hildenbrand, W., and J. F. Mertens (1972): “Upper Hemi-Continuity of the Equilibrium Correspondence for Pure Exchange Economies,” Econometrica, 40, 99–108. Housman, D. (1988): “Infinite Player Noncooperative Games and the Continuity of the Nash Equilibrium Correspondence,” Mathematics of Operations Research, 13, 488–496. 19

Khan, M., and Y. Sun (1999): “Non-Cooperative Games on Hyperfinite Loeb Spaces,” Journal of Mathematical Economics, 31, 455–492. (2002): “Non-Cooperative Games with Many Players,” in Handbook of Game Theory, Volume 3, ed. by R. Aumann, and S. Hart. Elsevier, Holland. Mas-Colell, A. (1983): “Walrasian Equilibria as Limits of Noncooperative Equilibria. Part I: Mixed Strategies,” Journal of Economic Theory, 30, 153–170. Novshek, W., and H. Sonnenschein (1983): “Walrasian Equilibria as Limits of Noncooperative Equilibria. Part II: Pure Strategies,” Journal of Economic Theory, 30, 171–187.

20

Approximation and Characterization of Nash Equilibria ...

Mar 18, 2012 - file in a game with a continuum of players is a Nash equilibrium if and ...... ∂A; if A0,...,An are finitely many subsets of Z, then ∂(. ⋃n i=0. Ai) ⊆.

213KB Sizes 2 Downloads 304 Views

Recommend Documents

Treewidth and Pure Nash Equilibria
1 Institute of Theoretical Computer Science, ETH Zurich,. CH-8092 Zurich .... implicitly provided in [19], that associates pure with approximate mixed equi- libria.

On computation and characterization of robust Nash ...
provide some answers to these problems and have recently gained a lot of interest. In game theory, we can distinguish at least two sources of uncertainties. They can emerge from the fact that a player has only partial or raw information about his act

Further Results on the Existence of Nash Equilibria ... - Semantic Scholar
University of Chicago. May 2009 ... *Financial support from the National Science Foundation (SES#9905599, SES#0214421) is gratefully ac# knowledged.

A characterization of the Nash bargaining solution - Springer Link
2 Department of Economics, 260 Heady Hall, Iowa State University, Ames,. Iowa 50011, USA (e-mail address: [email protected]; http://volij.co.il). 3 Department of ...

Long-term Nash equilibria in electricity markets
various long-term equilibria that can be analyzed with the appropriate tools. We present a ... The application of the proposed methodology is illustrated with several realistic ... their rivals; for regulators, because market power monitoring and.

A characterization of the Nash bargaining solution - Springer Link
Nir Dagan1, Oscar Volij2, Eyal Winter3. 1 Academic Priority Ltd., Rashi 31, 52015 Ramat-Gan, Israel. (e-mail: [email protected]; http://www.nirdagan.com).

Finding Multiple Nash Equilibria in Pool-Based Markets
companies (GENCOs) optimize their strategic bids anticipating the solution of the .... straints of the ISO problem come from the energy balance and the limits on the ... better alternative than solving the combinatorial game creating combinations ...

Algorithmic Computation and Approximation of ...
Some categories have multiple criteria to classify subcategories. ... measures that can be used to compute semantic similarity on other kinds of ontologies. ...... meaningful to use a σc threshold because in applications such as search engines,.

Synthesis and spectroscopic characterization of double ... - Arkivoc
Dec 4, 2016 - with the elaboration at positions 2, 3 or 6, depending on the application ..... CHaHbO), 4.32 (dd, J 5.9, 11.7 Hz, 1H, CHaHbO), 4.80 (d, J2.0 Hz, ...

Characterization and Parameterized Generation of ...
The development of new architectures for Field-Programmable Gate Arrays ..... is analogous to the conclusions of Shew 63] who studied the application of.

SYNTHESIS AND CHARACTERIZATION OF ...
1 Faculty of Chemical Technology, Hanoi University of Technology. 2 Institute of .... their different degrees of ionization depending on pH values. Actually, the ...

Characterization of the Psychological, Physiological and ... - CiteSeerX
Aug 31, 2011 - inhibitors [8], acetylcholine esterase inhibitors [9] and metabolites ...... Data was stored on a dedicated windows XP laptop PC for post.

SYNTHESIS, CHARACTERIZATION AND ANTIBACTERIAL ...
SYNTHESIS, CHARACTERIZATION AND ANTIBACTE ... T C-4 OF 7-HYDROXY-4- METHYL COUMARIN.pdf. SYNTHESIS, CHARACTERIZATION AND ...

Electrochemical Synthesis and Characterization of ...
atom of DPA.[11] The band around .... (1991). Electron localization and charge transport in poly(o-toluidine): A model polyaniline derivative. Phys. Rev. B 43 ...

Fabrication and characterization of pentacene-based ... - CiteSeerX
Feb 9, 2008 - transistors with a room-temperature mobility of 1.25 cm. 2. /Vs. Hoon-Seok Seo, Young-Se Jang, Ying Zhang, P. Syed Abthagir, Jong-Ho Choi*.

SYNTHESIS AND CHARACTERIZATION OF ...
DA = 70 %, determined by IR analysis [3]), pentasodium tripolyphosphate or TPP ... pH values were monitored by a digital Denver Instruments pH-meter with a ...

Synthesis and spectroscopic characterization of double ... - Arkivoc
Dec 4, 2016 - Such derivatives are used as reagents in organic synthesis and, due to their interest from the biological point of view, in the preparation of ...

Characterization of the Psychological, Physiological and ... - CiteSeerX
Aug 31, 2011 - free thinking when eyes were closed and significantly altered the global and ... comfortably at a desk facing a computer screen. Eight subjects ..... application into Chinese and loan of two choice reaction testing software,.

PREPARATION AND CHARACTERIZATION OF Ho3+TiO2 LASER ...
PREPARATION AND CHARACTERIZATION OF Ho3+Ti ... ACTIVE MEDIUM USING SOL-GEL TECHNIQUE.pdf. PREPARATION AND CHARACTERIZATION OF ...

Characterization and Parameterized Generation of ...
Natural Sciences and Engineering Research Council of Canada and Hewlett. Packard. ... J. Rose is with the Department of Electrical and Computer Engineering,. University of ..... 1) Boundaries on In/Out-Degree (pre degree.c): To assign ...... spent th

Preparation and characterization of venlafaxine ...
1Department of Chemistry, Faculty of Science, The Maharaja Sayajirao University of Baroda, Vadodara 390002, .... ingredients with varying degree of effectiveness and ... India). All other reagents used were of analytical grade. Preparation of CS and

Characterization and Parameterized Generation of ...
of the University of North Carolina (MCNC) 74] have collected approximately 200 public. 1 ... for large circuits (where there are no available benchmarks). ... is crucial to understand the type of data that the FPGA or algorithm will be required ....

SYNTHESIS, CHARACTERIZATION AND ANTIBACTERIAL ...
encouragement, quiet patience, devotion and love. Dana M. Hussein. Page 3 of 152. SYNTHESIS, CHARACTERIZATION AND ANTIBACTE ... T C-4 OF 7-HYDROXY-4- METHYL COUMARIN.pdf. SYNTHESIS, CHARACTERIZATION AND ANTIBACTE ... T C-4 OF 7-HYDROXY-4- METHYL COUM

Morphological and molecular characterization of Ptychodiscus ...
Carmen Campos Panisse 3, E-11500, Puerto de Santa Marıa, Spain. Dajun Qiu. CAS Key Laboratory of Tropical Marine Bio-resources and Ecology, South China Sea Institute of Oceanology, Chinese Academy of Science, Guangzhou, China. John D. Dodge. The Old